公 法 评 论 |
惟愿公平如大水滚滚,使公义如江河滔滔! |
The Effect of Constitutional Borrowings on the Drafting of South Africa's Bill of Rights and Interpretation of Human Rights Provisions
Jeremy Sarkin
Introduction
The Interim Constitution
The Constitutional Court
Comparative and International Law in the Constitutional Court
Conclusion
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
THE EFFECT OF CONSTITUTIONAL BORROWINGS ON THE DRAFTING OF SOUTH AFRICA'S
BILL OF RIGHTS AND INTERPRETATION OF HUMAN RIGHTS PROVISIONS
Jeremy Sarkin *
I. Introduction
One can only understand the extent and effect of constitutional borrowing
in a particular state if the historical and socio-legal context of that country
is understood.[1]
The early 1990's saw the unprecedented negotiation of a new dispensation in South Africa, resulting in profound changes to the country's social, political and economic structures.[2] Many of these changes are codified in the interim Constitution (the "IC"), including an entrenched justiciable Bill of Rights,[3] which became the supreme law of the land on April 27, 1994.[4] The inclusion of justiciable rights was an unique event since the constitutions adopted in 1910, 1961 and 1983 all provided for parliamentary supremacy.[5] Another feature of the interim Constitution was the creation of a Constitutional Assembly tasked with drafting the final Constitution between 1994 and 1996.[6] This Constitution was adopted at the end of 1996 and came into force on February 4, 1997.[7]
In drafting the Constitution, South Africa followed the recent trend discernible elsewhere of borrowing from international instruments, national constitutions and international and foreign decisions in order to benefit from the lessons learned by others.[8] This international trend toward comparative analysis and borrowing is particularly prevalent where new democracies emerging from years of domination and repression seek to entrench democracy and provide protection from human rights abuses. Constitutional borrowing occurs because the drafters of new constitutions often seek the assistance of lawyers from states with constitutions and a history of constitutional adjudication, since domestic experience in such endeavors is usually limited. These lawyers bring with them their own experiences of constitutional systems, which are then incorporated, to some degree, in the constitution that they are helping to draft.[9]
International and foreign experience substantially affected the process of constitutional drafting in South Africa and has already had a major effect on the constitutional and human rights adjudication that has taken place since 1994.[10] Lessons learned in the international arena are evident throughout both the interim and final Constitutions. Areas influenced included the structure of the state, the structure of the court system, and, most prominently, the content and language of the two bills of rights.[11] In addition to the indirect effects of international and comparative laws and decisions, both the interim and final Constitutions have explicit provisions that impact the reception and role of international and comparative law in constitutional adjudication.[12]3[9]4[1] This article examines the extent to which international and foreign law impacted the drafting of the interim Constitution and how the expanded role of international and comparative law has impacted the South African legal system.[13] Only the interim Constitution is evaluated and not the final Constitution, as part of the evaluation examines the role of the Constitutional Court in the development of the final Constitution. The effect of international experience is also examined to determine why a separate and distinct Constitutional Court was introduced into the domestic court system.[14]
The particular socio-political context in South Africa accounts to some degree for South African acceptance, in theory at least, of international law and comparative experience.[15] Therefore, this article reviews a few selected Constitutional Court decisions where this body of law could, and did, play a critical role to examine whether reliance on these bodies of law substantially shaped the interpretation of the South African interim Constitution and Bill of Rights.[16]
While the Constitution enjoins the courts to consider international law and makes it permissible to apply foreign law, [17]6[1] the courts may depart from these laws. Thus, while there has been a great deal of reliance on international and comparative law in South Africa, with the courts extensively citing such laws and decisions, the courts have also often departed from these positions or quoted from them selectively in support of the decision being handed down.[18]17[7]18[9]
II. The Interim Constitution
The shift from parliamentary to constitutional supremacy is probably the most
critical shift to occur during the transition to democracy in South Africa.[19]
Until the introduction of a justiciable constitution in April 1994, Parliament
was sovereign and there was no check on state power.[20] Thus, the legislature
could adopt any law and the courts had only a procedural reviewing function.[21]
The legal system in apartheid South Africa was a mixture of statute and hybrid common law, largely comprised of Roman-Dutch law and elements of English law.[22] During the apartheid years, South Africa had little regard for international or comparative law. The country was seen by many, including the United Nations and other international bodies, as a pariah.[23] Similarly, the South African government considered the United Nations an enemy and accorded scant regard to the various decisions and documents emanating from that organization.[24]
In 1989, the South African Law Commission explained the irrelevance of international law and its inability to impact the South African situation:
It cannot be envisaged that human rights norms as enshrined in international law can to any extent play a part - let alone a significant part - in the decision of the protection of group and individual rights in South Africa. Safety does not lie in the hope that our courts will apply the norms of international law.[25]
This view was grounded in the fact that for almost half a century the apartheid state had defied the United Nations and dismissed its Universal Declaration of Human Rights as communist propaganda.[26] The regime also vilified the declarations and resolutions of various United Nations agencies.[27]
As a result of South Africa's isolation and resistance to international law, South African lawyers and judges generally lacked knowledge and experience about the meaning of these documents, [28] about how they came to be adopted, and about how they could shape and influence the content of South African law once a constitutional system became the order of the day.[29] This created an opportunity for lawyers from other countries to participate in different ways in the drafting of both the interim and final Constitutions.[30]
Various draft versions of bills of rights were published between 1990 and 1994. [31] Although most emanated from political parties, one was drafted by the South African Law Commission and another, A Charter for Social Justice, was authored by a group of independent progressive lawyers from the Western Cape.[32] All these proposals borrowed from the international experience. This is especially true of the Charter for Social Justice, whose drafters were mainly academic lawyers, mostly with foreign study backgrounds, who extensively studied other constitutions and bills of rights.[33]
The impact of these various draft bills of rights has been noted by the drafters of the interim Bill of Rights, particularly in relation to it structure and grammar.[34] They noted that, in regard to specific wording, the technical committee relied on proposals framed in "suitably broad language" and thus looked to the Charter for Social Justice, the Democratic Party's draft bill of rights and various sections of the African National Congress's draft bill.[35] The drafters also noted that, in addition, the technical committee also looked to analogously framed bills of rights in other countries, including the German Basic Law and the Canadian Constitution.[36] Similarly, the impact of international human rights documents and the experiences of other countries were also examined.[37]
As the democratic state of South Africa rejoined the community of nations, previously scorned international covenants and other documents have been signed and ratified.[38] Thus, this body of law has taken on greater significance than before, although the extent of its practical role can be questioned.
The expanded role of international law is explicitly addressed in section 231(4) of the interim Constitution which provides, "The rules of customary international law binding on the Republic shall, unless inconsistent with this Constitution or an Act of Parliament, form part of the law of the Republic." [39] Thus, a particular human rights standard, which has become accepted as a rule of customary international law, must be implemented by a South African court in a decision, unless this rule is incompatible with the Constitution or an Act of Parliament. The proviso sets an important limit, permitting parliamentary supremacy in this area as in the past. As then-Chief Justice Rumpff stated in 1978 in Nduli and Another v. Minister of Justice and Others, "[c]ustomary international law must give way to South African legislation if that legislation is clear."[40]
International treaties also play a role in domestic South African law since both constitutions provide that the President can negotiate and sign international agreements.[41] However, as a check on presidential power, the interim Constitution provided that until a treaty was incorporated into South African law by an Act of Parliament, it was not legally binding within the country or domestically enforceable.[42] Furthermore, the signed agreement may not be inconsistent with the Constitution.[43] Thus, the few human rights agreements to which South Africa is party,[44] will play a direct role in the law only after Parliament so provides. [45] The final Constitution provides that international agreements, except for agreements which are technical, administrative or executive in nature, are binding on the Republic only after they have been approved by resolution in both houses of Parliament, the National Assembly and the National Council of Provinces.[46] In addition, an international agreement becomes law in South Africa only "when it is enacted into law by national legislation."[47] However, a self-executing provision of an agreement approved by Parliament is law unless inconsistent with the Constitution or an Act of Parliament.[48] Likewise, customary international law is binding on South Africa unless inconsistent with the Constitution or an Act of Parliament.[49] The courts are required, when interpreting the Bill of Rights to, "consider international law,"[50] and "may consider foreign law."[51]
International influences also impacted the debate over which rights ought to be incorporated into the interim Bill of Rights. This controversial issue was fiercely debated by two main camps - the minimalists and the optimalists.[52] The minimalists, represented mainly by the African National Congress (ANC), argued that the power to decide on inclusions or exclusions in an interim bill of rights should not be in the hands of negotiators who had not been elected and were therefore lacking democratic legitimacy.[53] The optimalists, on the other hand, represented mainly by the white government, wanted as many rights included, with maximum detail, before majority rule began.[54] As a result of necessary compromise, the interim Bill of Rights contained only those fundamental rights which negotiators could agree warranted protection during the transitional period before a final constitution was adopted. While controversial subjects such as abortion and the death penalty were discussed during negotiations, they were avoided during the drafting of the interim Bill of Rights on the basis that such issues should be left for resolution in the drafting of the final Constitution.[55]
In addition, according to two of the technical drafters of the interim Bill of Rights, Lourens du Plessis and Hugh Corder, international instruments such as the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (1948); the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966); the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1966); and the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms (1950) served as sources of inspiration.[56] Moreover, when there was controversy about the form of provisions, the Technical Committee responsible for drafting sought compromise in the wordings of these instruments.[57] Thus, for example, Section 8(3)(a), dealing with affirmative action, is styled after a comparable provision in Article 1(4) of the International Convention on the Elimination of all Forms of Racial Discrimination.[58]
The drafters also referred to the Bills of Rights of other countries,[59] specifically the German Basic Law (1949), the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms (1982), and the Chapter on Fundamental Human Rights and Freedoms in the Constitution of the Republic of Namibia (1990).[60] Thus many sections of the interim Bill of Rights have origins, or at least comparable sections, in other bills of rights.
However, even more important to constitutional adjudication in South Africa, was Section 35(1) of the interim Constitution:
In interpreting the provisions of this Chapter a court of law shall promote the values which underlie an open and democratic society based on freedom and equality and shall, where applicable, have regard to public international law applicable to the protection of the rights entrenched in this Chapter, and may have regard to comparable foreign case law.[61]
Thus, public international law is directly implicated in the South African legal system. The role that it plays is governed by the wording of this section, which states that a court "shall, where applicable" have regard to these standards.[62] The phrase both imposes an obligation and confers discretion onto the courts to refer to and utilize these legal principles when performing their interpretive task.[63] Since many of the rights provided by Chapter 3 of the interim Constitution, and Chapter 2 of the final Constitution, have internationally comparable provisions, public international law, as applied by means of Section 35(1) of the interim Constitution, assumes broad significance.[64]
Like all other bills of rights, the interim Bill of Rights adopted in South Africa is a written text transmitting meaning by way of language. In the South African constitutional setting, as in arguably all settings, the language of a legal text can be meaningless in the absence of context. Policy questions and value judgements are the keys to interpreting and understanding judicial decisions, given the wide scope of judicial review. Language, itself, is only one factor to be weighed in evaluating constitutional decisions, and these decisions cannot be understood unless considered in relation to the values subscribed to by the judges who themselves interpret the constitution. This kind of interpretation is not exact and is often about making political choices.[65]
To determine the meaning of certain words, the courts might look to the ends they seek to achieve.[66] The limited usefulness of actual language is expressed by Section 35(2), which has its origins in Canadian and German law.[67] Section 35(2) states:
No law which limits any of the rights entrenched in this Chapter, shall be constitutionally invalid solely by reason of the fact that the wording used prima facie exceeds the limits imposed in this Chapter, provided such a law is reasonably capable of a more restricted interpretation which does not exceed such limits, in which event such law shall be construed as having a meaning in accordance with the said more restricted interpretation.[68]
Section 35(2) thus constitutionalizes the procedure known as "verfassungskonforme Auslegung" in Germany and "reading down" in Canada.[69] This procedure provides that no law shall be invalid solely because a prima facie reading of the words used suggests that it exceeds the limits imposed in the Bill of Rights as long as a more limited interpretation is possible.[70]
The impact of international and comparative law is also found in the limitation section, Section 33, of the interim Constitution. Section 33(1), reads:
The rights entrenched in this Chapter may be limited by law of general application,
provided that such limitation--
(a) shall be permissible only to the extent that it is--
(i) reasonable; and
(ii) justifiable in an open and democratic society based on freedom and equality[71];
and
(b) shall not negate the essential content of the right in question
and provided further that any limitation to--
(aa) a right entrenched in section 10, 11, 12, 14(1), 21, 25 or 30(1)(d) or
(e) or (2); or
(bb) a right entrenched in section 15, 16, 17, 18, 23 or 24, in so far as
such right relates to free and fair political activity, shall, in addition
to being reasonable as required in paragraph (a)(i), also be necessary.[72]
The requirement that a limitation must be accomplished through law of general application reflects Article 19(1) of the German Basic Law.[73] Similarly, the stipulation in Section 33(1)(b) that limitations on rights "shall not negate the essential content of the right in question" is reminiscent of Article 19(2) of the German Basic Law,[74] which states that in "no case may the core element of a basic right be encroached upon."[75]
The limitation clause also owes a debt to Section 1 of the Canadian Charter. Section 1 states, "The Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms guarantees the rights and freedoms set out in it subject only to such reasonable limits prescribed by law as can be demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society."[76] The drafters of the interim Constitution critically examined the Canadian case of Regina v Oakes[77] to extract the criteria for determining what is reasonable and demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society. Oakes considered the values at the core of Section 1.[78]
The Oakes decision profoundly impacted the drafting of the interim Constitution. In Oakes, the Canadian Supreme Court decided it would follow a two-stage process as the method of judicial review.[79] The first stage requires the applicant to show how the legislation in question infringes upon the rights and freedoms enshrined in the Charter, both as a matter of interpretation and also as a matter of fact.[80] In the second stage, the Court determines whether the law adopted is reasonable and demonstrably justifiable.[81] This allows the state to justify the law by reference to its purpose and also its concurrence with a three-part proportionality test. To pass this hurdle in Oakes, the state had to show the following:
First, the measures adopted must be carefully designed to achieve the objective in question. They must not be arbitrary, unfair or based on irrational considerations. In short, they must be rationally connected to the objective. Second, the means, even if rationally connected to the objective in this first sense, should impair "as little as possible" the right or freedom in question. Third, there must be a proportionality between the effects of the measures which are responsible for limiting the Charter right or freedom, and the objective which has been identified as of "sufficient importance."[82]
These principles were absorbed into the interim Constitution, particularly in the limitation clause.[83]
The limitation section also has some roots in the European Convention on Human Rights. In making the Sunday Times[84] decision, the European Court of Human Rights noted that:
The following are two of the requirements that flow from the expression "prescribed by law." Firstly, the law must be adequately accessible: The citizen must be able to have an indication that is adequate in the circumstances of the legal rules applicable to a given case. Secondly, a norm cannot be regarded as "law" unless it is formulated with sufficient precision to enable the citizen to regulate his conduct: He must be able - if need be with appropriate advice--to foresee, to a degree that is reasonable in the circumstances, the consequences which a given action may entail. Those consequences need not be foreseeable with absolute certainty: Experience shows this to be unattainable.[85]
Section 33(1)(a) further demands that a law, when it impinges on a right, must meet the test of being "reasonable" and "justifiable in an open and democratic society based on freedom and equality."[86] Thus, the interim Constitution called for proportionality: The various rights and laws impinging on those rights must be balanced.
The principle of proportionality is found in various international and national contexts. It has been used to interpret the European Convention so limits can be placed on rights "only when it is necessary in the light of the interests advanced as weighed against the requirements of a democratic society."[87] Proportionality is a testing principle in a number of other countries in Europe, [88] and requires striking a balance between the competing interests by weighing the advantages and disadvantages of the measure.[89] In Germany, for example, when an individual's rights are to be affected, the state has to meet three requirements - suitability, necessity and proportionality.[90] The courts, in that country, have incorporated proportionality within the principle of the "least detrimental settlement."[91]
The European experience is also evident in the inclusion in the interim Constitution's limitation clause of the term "democratic society."[92] Sieghardt points to the need for attention to:
[T]he needs or objectives of a democratic society in relation to the right or freedom concerned; without a notion of such needs, the limitations essential to support them cannot be evaluated. For example, freedom of expression is based on the need of a democratic society to promote the individual self-fulfillment of its members, the attainment of truth, participation in decision-making and the striking of a balance between stability and change. The aim is to have a pluralistic, open, tolerant society. This necessarily involves a delicate balance between the wishes of the individual and the utilitarian "greater good of the majority." But democratic societies approach this problem from the standpoint of the importance of the individual, and the undesirability of restricting his or her freedom.[93]
Comparative jurisprudence was also used to determine whether the term "necessary" should be included in the clause. "Necessary" was defined by the European Court in the Handyside case[94] as distinct from "indispensable," "useful," "reasonable," or "desirable."[95] The court held that the context had to be looked at to determine what was necessary within the "reality of the pressing social need."[96]
Similarly, the drafters borrowed from American jurisprudential concepts in drafting the limitations clause. The drafters introduced strict scrutiny to the limitations section through a clause of the interpretation provision.[97] As a result, certain rights in the interim Constitution were protected by the strict scrutiny standard found in American constitutional jurisprudence.[98]
III. The Constitutional Court
The view prevailed during negotiations that most of the judges appointed prior
to the transition were unsuited to decide constitutional issues because of
their training, experience and temperament.[99] Historically, the judiciary
had been drawn from a very small segment of the population.[100] With the
exception of one recent appointment, all of the approximately 130 Supreme
Court judges were white and all accept one were male.[101] At the end of 1988
all of the 144 regional court magistrates were white, while of 782 district
court magistrates, 768 were white, ten were Indian, four were colored and
none was black.[102] Undoubtedly, the fact that the legal system was faced
with a crisis of legitimacy was due in part to its composition.[103] Whatever
their personal political preferences, judges had spent their years on the
bench submitting to the heavy hand of the executive. [104] In the past judges
attempted to explain their role in the positivist tradition, as declarers
of the law and not its makers.[105] However, criticism of the judges has often
been predicated on a wider view of the judicial function.[106] The Law Commission
favored a constitutional court based in the Appellate Division,[107] while
the Association of Law Societies of the Republic of South Africa--the attorneys--proposed
that the Supreme Court be granted jurisdiction to hear constitutional and
human rights matters.[108] The Appellate Division would then hear appeals
on constitutional and human rights matters and other appeals on points of
law only.[109] The African National Congress, however, supported the creation
of a constitutional court above the Appellate Division to adjudicate on constitutional
and human rights issues only. International experience was also invoked in
support of the need for a constitutional court.[110]
The belief was that to leave the judiciary as then composed--exclusively white and almost exclusively male--while conferring on it the added powers of judicial review, would be to allow law democratically enacted by the majority to be overturned by a court composed of a partisan and insulated minority. [111] Some argued for the decentralization of the constitutional powers of the courts.[112] Within this model, as in the United States, all courts would have constitutional testing powers and would be able to strike down legislation or administrative acts that overstepped constitutional boundaries.[113]
South African critics of the decentralized model argued that even if more new judges were appointed, the old judges would still benefit from the enhanced judicial powers for which they were ill suited.[114] Proponents of a constitutional court therefore argued that only one court, meticulously selected and well balanced, should have the powers of constitutional review.[115] Criticism of the central court idea came from those who believed that such appointments would be more politically inspired than the elevation of judges from other courts.[116] These critics argued that granting all courts review powers would ensure that a human rights culture would permeate the entire legal order.[117] They further argued that judges deciding constitutional issues should not be insulated from the cut and thrust of daily courtroom litigation, as this is an essential element of judicial experience and provides the necessary training and proficiency for constitutional adjudication.
In terms of the interim Constitution, the outcome of this debate was the creation of the Constitutional Court, above the Appellate Division, to adjudicate on constitutional and human rights issues only.[118] Under the interim Constitution, the Appellate Division was denied jurisdiction "to adjudicate any matter within the jurisdiction of the Constitutional Court."[119] In the final Constitution, however, all the higher courts are given powers of constitutional review,[120] except the power to strike down a parliamentary statute, resides only with the Constitutional Court which must affirm the decision of the lower court before the lower court's decision has the force of law.[121]
The procedure for appointing judges to the Constitutional Court is set out in the interim Constitution.[122] Discussions over the procedure generated great controversy during the multi-party talks that preceded finalization of the Constitution. The controversy reflected recognition that the judicial appointments might determine the outcome of constitutional decisions. To protect the judicial structure and maintain public confidence in the legitimacy of the Court's decisions, the drafters sought to avoid a politicized appointment system. Thus, the drafters departed from the highly political appointment procedure followed in the United States.[123]
The interim Constitution provided that the President of the Constitutional Court and the ten other judges[124] are appointed for a non-renewable period of seven years,[125] and must be South African citizens,[126] who are "fit and proper person[s]."[127] Further, the interim Constitution required that candidates either be judges of the Supreme Court, have been advocates, attorneys or law lecturers for a minimum of ten years,[128] or, as a result of training or experience, have expertise in the field of constitutional law.[129] Not more than two judges could be chosen from this latter category of persons.[130] In fact all eleven judges appointed were lawyers. The composition has, and will continue to have, profound repercussions for the type of decisions handed down. Non-lawyers on the Court might have ensured a movement away from a strict legalistic approach.
Under the Constitution, the President of the Court must be appointed by the President of South Africa, "in consultation with the cabinet and after consultation with the Chief Justice."[131] The President, however, must choose the President of the Court from a list of four names supplied by the Judicial Services Commission. The first appointment to the office of President of the Court was exempted from this requirement,[132] and the President was left free to appoint any person who met the requirements laid down for appointment.[133]
Arthur Chaskalson was appointed first President of the Constitutional Court. Four more of the judges of the Court were appointed from the ranks of existing judges by President Mandela, "in consultation with the Cabinet and with the Chief Justice."[134] Sitting judges, therefore, make up a large component of the Court, but those selected represented the more progressive sector of the existing judiciary.
Following the interim Constitution's requirements, the remaining six judges of the Constitutional Court were appointed by the President, "in consultation with the cabinet and after consultation with the President of the Constitutional Court."[135] For the first set of appointments, the six were selected from a motivated list of ten submitted by the Judicial Service Commission.[136] Had Mandela not wanted to appoint any of the nominees, he would have had to furnish reasons to the Commission,[137] and the Judicial Service Commission would have been required to provide another list of names from which the President would have been obliged to appoint six judges.[138]
In 1994, the Judicial Service Commission had seventeen members, who were:
(1) the Chief Justice, who shall preside at meetings of the Commission (Judge
M. Corbett);
(2) the President of the Constitutional Court (Judge A. Chaskalson);
(3) one Judge President designated by the Judge Presidents of the various
divisions of the Supreme Court (Judge J. A. Howard of Natal);
(4) the Minister responsible for the administration of justice or his or her
nominee (Advocate D. Omar);
(5-6) two practicing advocates designated by the advocates' profession (Advocate
Trengrove and Advocate Moerane);
(7-8) two practicing attorneys designated by the attorneys' profession (Mr.
L. van Zyl and Mr. N. Mojapelo);
(9) one professor of law designated by the deans of all the law faculties
at South African universities (Professor E. Mureinik of the University of
the Witwatersrand);
(10-13) four senators designated en bloc by the Senate by resolution adopted
by a majority of at least two-thirds of all its members (I. Direko, E. Mchunu
and B. Ngcuka, all of the ANC, and R. Radue of the National Party); and
(14-17) four persons, two of whom shall be practicing attorneys or advocates,
who shall be designated by the President in consultation with the Cabinet
(D. Gordon SC, G. Bizos SC, K. Moroka, and J. Erentsen).
On the occasion of the consideration of matters specifically relating to a provincial division of the Supreme Court, the Judge President of the relevant division and the premier of the relevant province are included as part of the Commission as well.[139] Crucially, the Commission is and will continue to be composed largely of members of the legal profession.[140]
The process of appointment to the Constitutional Court has played and will play a pivotal role in determining the character of the bench, marking a distinct departure from the judiciary of the apartheid order. The dominance of older white men has given way to a diversity in age, gender, religion and outlook. [141] This has had a major effect on the type of decision handed down by the Court, although the narrow spectrum of political leanings among the Justices of the Constitutional Court is of crucial significance.[142] It is not surprising, therefore, that a high level of concurrence has characterized the decisions of the court to date.[143] In addition, several of the rulings indicate that the Court will permit Parliament to decide policy and govern with very limited judicial hindrance.[144]
However, many of the decisions of the Court are victories for democracy and human rights. Decisions handed down include the abolition of the death penalty[145] and juvenile corporal punishment as sentencing options,[146] the outlawing of civil imprisonment for debt,[147] and the recognition of a right of access to police dockets and to consult state witnesses.[148] Additionally, many decisions were related to the right to a fair trial, as well as to issues of equality,[149] privacy,[150] freedom of expression,[151] provincial powers,[152] and the application of the Bill of Rights.[153]
IV. Comparative and International Law in the Constitutional Court
General international experience indicates that national courts often look
to international human rights instruments, foreign law and foreign judicial
opinions for assistance in interpreting their domestic human rights documents.
Therefore, the relevance and usefulness of international and comparative law
in the context of South African judicial interpretation--as opposed to constitutional
creation--merits examination.[154]
This comparative process assists judges in defining the meaning of various clauses that have counterparts in international law, assessing what is reasonable, and in determining reasonable limitations on rights.[155] The use of these bodies of law by the Constitutional Court can be determined by examining the role they have played in various decisions by the Court.
The death penalty case of State v. Makwanyane and Another,[156] was the first case heard by the Constitutional Court.[157] Argument took place before the Court between February 15 and February 17, 1995.[158] The judgment, handed down on June 6, 1995, considered Section 277 of the Criminal Procedure Act and unanimously declared the death penalty unconstitutional.[159] The main judgment, with which all the other justices concurred, although sometimes for differing reasons, was written by the Court's President, Justice Arthur Chaskalson.[160]
The Court determined that use of the death penalty would violate Section 11(2) of the Constitution which reads: "No person shall be subject to torture of any kind, whether physical, mental or emotional, nor shall any person be subject to cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment."[161] Various other provisions of the Constitution were also found relevant to the inquiry, including the right to life, which reads: "Every person shall have the right to life;"[162] and the right to dignity which reads: "Every person shall have the right to respect for and protection of his or her dignity."[163] The Court also investigated arbitrariness and inequality in the imposition of the death penalty.[164]
In arriving at its decision, the Court considered foreign law on the topic. The Court considered the decisions of the courts of Hungary, Tanzania, the Privy Council and the European Court of Human Rights.[165] In Makwanyane, the Court stated that both binding and non-binding public international law may be used as tools of interpretation:
International agreements and customary international law provide a framework within which Chap[ter] 3 can be evaluated and understood, and for that purpose decisions of tribunals dealing with comparable instruments, such as the United Nations Committee on Human Rights, the Inter-American Commission on Human Rights, and the European Court of Human Rights, and in appropriate cases, reports of specialized agencies such as the International Labour Organization may provide guidance as to the correct interpretation of particular provisions.[166]
The Court also held in Makwanyane that comparable bills of rights and their jurisprudence would have enhanced importance until South Africa developed its own indigenous jurisprudence.[167]
The Constitutional Court has stated, however, that foreign cases will not provide clear answers to questions around the interpretation of the South African Bill of Rights. In fact, various statements from the court have warned against the use of foreign law because of the "different contexts within which other constitutions were drafted, the different social structures and milieu existing in those countries as compared with those in this country, and the different historical backgrounds against which the various constitutions came into being."[168]
In a case which went to the Constitutional Court on abstract review, the court was asked to rule on the constitutional validity of the controversial Gauteng School Education Bill.[169] The argument put to the Court was that certain sections of the law conflicted with various rights entrenched in the interim Constitution.[170] The possibly offending sections of the local bill prohibited public schools from conducting language-competence tests as an admission requirement, and placed a duty on schools to promote a policy which fostered respect for different religious tenets and protected the right of pupils not to attend religious instruction classes.[171]
Reviewing the Constitution and interpreting the relevant sections, the Court found that the law was not unconstitutional in respect of the objections raised by the petitioners. Justice Mahomed wrote the main opinion in which he referred to the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms and cases decided by the Canadian courts, considering Charter provisions and French and English language requirements in Canadian schools.[172] Justice Sachs wrote a concurring decision investigating the applicability and relevance of international human rights law to minority rights in South Africa, in particular whether minorities have the right to state educational institutions based on a common culture, language, or religion.[173] Justice Sachs examined the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, the International Covenant on Economic Social and Cultural Rights, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, the role of the League of Nations and the United Nations in promoting and protecting human and minority rights as well as decisions of the Permanent Court of International Justice.[174] His conclusion was that, "the central theme that runs through the development of international human rights law in relation to protection of minorities, is that of preventing discrimination against disadvantaged and marginalised groups, guaranteeing them full and factual equality and providing for remedial action to deal with past discrimination."[175] Thus, in Justice Sachs' opinion, the principles of international law counseled against the Petitioners' claim for continual preference of the "functional majority" to maintain "language exclusivity in relatively affluent schools."[176]
Among the Court's more controversial decisions was the ruling upholding the validity of the amnesty provisions of the Truth Commission legislation, [177] despite strong arguments that they violated the right of access to court as well as norms of international law. At the crux of the battle over the constitutionality of the Promotion of National Unity and Reconciliation Act of 1995, Act 34,[178] was whether removing civil remedies from victims of human rights abuses was in conflict with the provision in the Constitution reading: "Every person shall have the right to have justiciable disputes settled by a court of law or, where appropriate, another independent and impartial forum."[179] The applicants relied partly on the argument that the Act violates a peremptory norm of international law which provides rights to individual victims of war crimes regardless of the attitude of the state. [180]
The decision of Azanian People's Organization and Others v. The President of the Republic of South Africa and Others was handed down on July 25, 1996, with the Court unanimously upholding the validity of Section 20(7) of the Promotion of National Unity and Reconciliation Act. [181] The main issues the court examined were whether the interim Constitution permitted amnesty and, if so, whether it permitted amnesty from criminal prosecution only or from civil liability as well.[182]
The Court began its evaluation of the constitutionality of the relevant section by agreeing that unless there is some provision in the Constitution which authorized violations of rights protected in the Constitution, then any law which violates those rights would be unconstitutional.[183] The Court then indicated how both the post-amble and Section 33(1) of the interim Constitution (the limitations clause) permitted rights protected by the Constitution to be circumscribed.[184] In evaluating whether amnesty is permissible for criminal acts, the Court noted that:
The Act seeks to address this massive problem by encouraging these survivors and the dependents of the tortured and the wounded, the maimed and the dead, to unburden their grief publicly, to receive the collective recognition of a new nation that they were wronged, and crucially, to help them to discover what did in truth happen to their loved ones, where and under what circumstances it did happen, and who was responsible. That truth, which the victims of repression seek so desperately to know is, in the circumstances, much more likely to be forthcoming if those responsible for such monstrous misdeeds are encouraged to disclose the whole truth with the incentive that they will not receive the punishment which they undoubtedly deserve if they do. Without that incentive there is nothing to encourage such persons to make the disclosures and to reveal the truth which persons in the positions of the applicants so desperately desire. With that incentive, what might unfold are objectives fundamental to the ethos of a new constitutional order.[185]
Noting further that Parliament "not only has the authority in terms of the epilogue to make a law providing for amnesty . . . it is in fact obliged to do so,"[186] the Court opined that the granting of amnesty is both necessary to achieve reconciliation and to "facilitate the consolidation of new democracies."[187] Moreover, this approach had been accepted in various other countries which also set up truth commissions to ameliorate similar historical difficulties.[188]
Unfortunately, in considering whether international law permits South Africa to grant amnesty, the Court narrowly found that the Constitution permits an Act of Parliament to override international law,[189] and that international law does not become enforceable in South Africa until it is "incorporated into the municipal law by legislative enactment."[190] However, despite this holding, the Court did find that, regardless of whether international law is trumped by domestic law, international law, particularly in the Geneva Protocols, did not outlaw amnesty, particularly with regard to the types of circumstances that existed in South Africa during the period under scrutiny.[191] The Court noted that international acceptance of truth commissions was based on a
distinction between the position of perpetrators of acts of violence in the course of war (or other conflicts between states or armed conflicts between liberation movements seeking self-determination against colonial and alien domination of their countries), on the one hand, and their position in respect of violent acts perpetrated during other conflicts which take place within the territory of a sovereign State in consequence of a struggle between the armed forces of that state and other dissident armed forces operating under responsible command, within such a State on the other. In respect of the latter category, there is no obligation on the part of a contracting state to ensure the prosecution of those who might have performed acts of violence or other acts which [sic] would ordinarily be characterized as serious invasions of human rights.[192]
Proceeding to consider whether the granting of amnesty in respect to civil liability is an infringement of constitutionally protected rights, the Court agreed that while amnesty is capable of being construed in the limited sense of immunity borrowed from criminal law, it is also capable of a much broader interpretation.[193] In arriving at the conclusion that amnesty includes immunity from civil liability, the Court stated:
Central to the justification of amnesty in respect of the criminal prosecution for offenses committed during the prescribed period with political objectives is the appreciation that the truth will not effectively be revealed by the wrongdoers if they are to be prosecuted for such acts. That justification must necessarily and unavoidably apply to the need to indemnify such wrongdoers against civil claims for payment of damages. Without that incentive the wrongdoer cannot be encouraged to reveal the whole truth which might inherently be against his or her material or proprietary interests. There is nothing in the language of the epilogue which persuades me that what the makers of the Constitution intended to do was to encourage wrongdoers to reveal the truth by providing for amnesty against criminal prosecution in respect of their acts but simultaneously to discourage them from revealing that truth by keeping intact the threat that such revelations might be visited with what might in many cases be very substantial claims for civil damages. It appears to me to be more reasonable to infer that the legislation contemplated in the epilogue would, in the circumstances defined, be wide enough to allow for an amnesty which would protect a wrongdoer who told the truth from both the criminal and the civil consequences of his or her admissions.[194]
Regarding the civil liability of the state for these wrongdoings, the Court asserted that constraints on resources are key to a determination of whether the state ought to bear responsibility for the harm and damages suffered by victims.[195] Evident here is the tendency for the Court to act reluctantly rather than robustly in certain matters. This tendency is apparent in at least eight highly political decisions,[196] including the Court's decision relating to the certification of the final Constitution.[197] These cases highlight the limited degree to which the Court has been willing to play an interventionist role and reflect the Court's extreme caution about interfering with political choices made by the government. A similar caution has been made evident in cases relating to resource allocation,[198] and it seems that resource prioritization will depend solely on government determination. In addition, various Constitutional Court opinions indicate the Court's inclination to allow Parliament to determine policy and govern with very little judicial interference. The following comment from the decision under discussion serves as illustration:
Those negotiators of the Constitution and leaders of the nation who were required to address themselves to these agonizing problems must have been compelled to make hard choices. They could have chosen to direct that the limited resources of the state be spent by giving preference to the formidable delictual claims of those who had suffered from acts of murder, torture or assault perpetrated by servants of the state, diverting to that extent, desperately needed funds in the crucial areas of education, housing and primary health care. They were entitled to permit a different choice to be made between competing demands inherent in the problem.[199]
In the same vein, the Court later stated that Parliament could have chosen to insist that a comprehensive amnesty manifestly involved an inequality of sacrifice between the victims and the perpetrators of invasions into the fundamental rights of such victims and their families. . . . They could have chosen to differentiate between the wrongful acts committed in defense of the old order and those committed in the resistance of it, or they could have chosen a comprehensive form of amnesty which [sic] did not make this distinction. Again they were entitled to make the latter choice. The choice of alternatives legitimately fell within the judgement of the lawmakers. The exercise of that choice does not, in my view, impact on its constitutionality.[200]
V. Conclusion
The expanded role of international and comparative law has had a marked impact
on the South African legal system. The particular context of South Africa's
Bill of Rights will remain crucial and imitative approaches that fail to account
for South Africa's unique situation are unlikely to be successful. Nevertheless,
international law and comparative lessons on constitutional adjudication and
interpretation will play a key role until a truly South African constitutional
jurisprudence emerges.
Constitutional decisions in South Africa and other countries suggest that the language of a bill of rights is only one among many factors guiding its interpretation. Words in a bill of rights are often vague, and the interpretation of expressions such as "life," "liberty," "equality," "security," and "equal protection" by individual judges is greatly affected by the judge's economic, political, and social values.[201] While the most important factor determining interpretation is the composition of the adjudicating court, factors such as public opinion also play a role. In Canada, for example, the Court has not focused on the words of the Charter and seldom on the legislative intent of the framers, but rather has adopted a "balancing approach."[202]
In spite of such reservations about the meaningfulness of the specific phraseology of a constitution and bill of rights, it is obviously true that language must be an important factor in judicial interpretation.[203] For this reason, both constitutional language and the manner in which various clauses have been interpreted in other domestic constitutions and international instruments are important in the South African context. How other courts have interpreted the rights to life, equality, dignity, freedom, security of the person, and so on, are important as a guide to South African courts. At the same time, when predicting the outcome of a decision, one cannot ignore the South African policy factors which will play their part. Thus, the context within which a matter is adjudicated, the politics of the country, as well as such factors as judicial appointment procedures, must be examined.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
[*] Associate Professor of Law, University of Western Cape, South Africa.
Visiting Professor of Law in 1998 at the Universities of Maryland, Cincinnati
and Oregon. B.A., L.L.B., University of Natal in South Africa, L.L.M., Harvard
Law School, Doctorate of Laws, University of the Western Cape.
[1] For some background discussion of the legal and social structures of South
Africa, see LAWRENCE BOULLE, ET AL., CONSTITUTIONAL AND ADMINISTRATIVE LAW:
BASIC PRINCIPLES 101-113 (1989); Jeremy Sarkin & Howard Varney, `Traditional
Weapons, Cultural Expediency and the Political Conflict in South Africa: A
Culture of Weapons and a Culture of Violence, `6 S. AFR. J. CRIM. JUST. 2,
2-4 (1993); `'Jeremy Sarkin, Preventive Detention in South Africa, in PREVENTIVE
DETENTION AND SECURITY LAW: A COMPARATIVE SURVEY 210, 210-20 (Andrew Harding
& John Hatchard eds., 1993).
[2] See generally Jeremy Sarkin, The Development of a Human Rights Culture
in South Africa, 20 HUM. RTS. Q. 628 (1998) (discussing the development of
the two constitutions and the restructuring of the government infrastructure
including the court and criminal justice system).
[3] See Etienne Mureinik, A Bridge to Where? Introducing the Interim Bill
of Rights, 10 S. AFR. J. HUM. RTS. 31, 33 (1994); see also S. AFR. CONST.
of 1993 (IC), ch. 3 (delimiting numerous "Fundamental Rights").
[4] See David Welsh, Negotiating a Democratic Constitution, in CHANGES IN
SOUTH AFRICA 25 (J.E. Spence ed., 1994).
[5] See Dion A. Basson, The Legislative Authority: The Relationship Between
Parliament and the Courts: Parliamentary Sovereignty (Section E), in SOUTH
AFRICAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 169-200 (Christina Van der Walt trans., 1988).
[6] See S. AFR. CONST. of 1993 (IC), ch. 5, Ё 68-74.
[7] See Proc. No. R. 6, 1997 (making February 4, 1997 the date of effectiveness
pursuant to Section 243 of the final Constitution).
[8] See, e.g., John Claydon & Jennie Hatfield, The Use of International
Human Rights Law to Interpret Canada's Charter of Rights and Freedoms 2 CONN.
J. INT'L L. 349, 354-59 (1987) (discussing the use of international sources
to interpret the meaning of the Canadian Bill of Rights, which like the South
African Bill of Rights, was influenced by external legal sources).
[9] For example, two American constitutional lawyers played a direct role
in drafting the Inkatha Freedom Party's Bill of Rights. The influence of the
United States legal system is also found in many places in the KwaZulu Bill
of Rights.
[10] See, e.g., State v. Makwanyane and Another, 1995 (3) SALR 391, 436-39
(CC) (considering numerous sources of foreign law when deciding the constitutionality
of the death penalty); see infra Section IV (discussing a number of seminal
cases decided under the interim Constitution).
[11] See S. AFR. CONST. of 1996, ch. 2 ("Bill of Rights"); S. AFR.
CONST. of 1993 (IC), ch. 3 ("Fundamental Rights").
[12] The most significant of these provisions in the final Constitution are
Sections 39 and 231 that mandate the use of foreign and international sources
in certain circumstances and determine the legal status of international agreements.
See S. AFR. CONST. of 1996, ch. 2, ?39(1)(b-c) (defining the use of the foreign
and public international law); id. at ch. 14, ?231 (defining the mechanisms
used to determine the legal status of international agreements). As will be
discussed, see infra text accompanying notes [ and , ]the interim Constitution
included similar provisions. See S. AFR. CONST. of 1993 (IC), ch. 3, ?35(a);
id. at ch. 14, ?231.
[13] See infra section II.
[14] See infra section III.
[15] See Johan D. van der Vyver, `Comparative Law in Constitutional Litigation,
111 S. AFR. L.J. 19 (1994) (using a judgement under the Declaration of Fundamental
Rights in the Bophuthatswana Constitution Act of 1977 to argue for the value
of understanding the intricacies of comparative law in constitutional litigation).
[16] See infra section IV. This section considers State v. Makwanyane and
Another, 1995 (3) SALR 391 (CC), In re Gauteng Education Bill of 1995, 1996
(3) SALR 165 (CC), and Azanian Peoples Organization (AZAPO) and Others v.
President of the Republic of South Africa and Others, 1996 (4) SALR 671 (CC).
[17] See infra note [ and accompanying text.
18] See infra text accompanying notes [ ]and [.
19] See S. AFR. CONST. of 1993 (IC), ch. 7, ?98(2) (granting the Constitutional
Court jurisdiction over all matters concerning Constitutional interpretation).
[20] See, e.g., Basson, supra note 5, at 169-200 (explaining that South African
constitutional law developed out of English constitutional law and, therefore,
judicial authority has traditionally been subordinate to legislative authority);
W. J. HOSTEN ET AL., INTRODUCTION TO SOUTH AFRICAN LAW AND LEGAL THEORY 597-634
(1977) (discussing in great detail the South African constitutional structure
and its historical influences).
[21] See Basson, supra note 5, at 190-91.
[22] See, e.g., WILLE'S PRINCIPLES OF SOUTH AFRICAN LAW 20-37 (Dale Hutchison
et al. eds., 8th ed. 1991) (explaining that Roman-Dutch law was used to create
the South African legal system which was later influenced in the early nineteenth
century by English law).
[23] See AUDIE KLOTZ, NORMS IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS: THE STRUGGLE AGAINST
APARTHEID 48-54 (1995) (discussing how the United Nations used a wide range
of diplomatic, military and economic sanctions to punish the apartheid regime).
[24] See CHRIS ALDEN, APARTHEID'S LAST STAND: THE RISE AND FALL OF THE SOUTH
AFRICAN SECURITY STATE 49 (1996) (pointing out that for white South Africans,
the United Nation's passage of a mandatory arms embargo against South Africa
represented a "multi-dimensional onslaught" against the country).
[25] South African Law Commission, Working Paper 25 Project 58 Group and Human
Rights at 182 (1989).
[26] For an extensive discussion of the tense relationship between the United
Nations and South Africa, see LOUIS B. SOHN, RIGHTS IN CONFLICT: THE UNITED
NATIONS AND SOUTH AFRICA 63-170 (1994); KLOTZ, supra note 32, at 3-12, 39-55.
[27] However, it is noteworthy that South Africa remained a member of the
United Nations, which it joined on November 7, 1945. See UNITED NATIONS, MEMBER
STATES (visited December 7, 1998) <http://www.un.org/Overview/unmember.html>.
[28] Lawyers from the exiled liberation movements, however, had studied abroad
and had been schooled in international and foreign law. These lawyers attended
law schools in different parts of the world including the United Kingdom,
the United States, Germany, Canada, Poland, Mozambique, Zambia, Lesotho and
Russia. South African academic lawyers had also studied abroad. The tradition,
however, was for those graduating from the Afrikaans law schools to study
mainly in Europe, specifically in Germany, Belgium and the Netherlands. Those
graduating from English law schools generally pursued graduate studies in
the United Kingdom although some went to the United States.
[29] In South Africa there was a debate in the mid-1980's on the need for
a bill of rights. Outside the country, conferences and other forums were held
to debate what a future South African Constitution and Bill of Rights ought
to contain. One such conference was held at Columbia University entitled,
"Human Rights in the Post-Apartheid South African Constitution."
See 21 COLUM. HUM. RTS. L. REV. (1989) (reprinting select papers from the
conference).
[30] See Jeremy Sarkin, The Role of the Legal Profession in the Promotion
and Advancement of a Human Rights Culture, Comm. L. BULL. 1306 (1995) (describing
the influential role of international lawyers in the drafting process due
to their much greater familiarity with a constitutional structure).
[31] For example, the African National Congress, the South African Law Commission,
the South African Government, the Democratic Party, the Inkatha Freedom Party,
the Association of Law Societies of the Republic of South Africa, and the
Equality Foundation all provided drafts. See LOURENS DU PLESSIS & HUGH
CORDER, UNDERSTANDING SOUTH AFRICA'S TRANSITIONAL BILL OF RIGHTS 48-51, 192-94
(1994) (providing an in-depth discussion of the constitutional drafting process
and an overview of each group's main goals).
[32] See HUGH CORDER ET AL., A CHARTER FOR SOCIAL JUSTICE (1992). The draft
was written by Hugh Corder, Steve Kahanovitz, John Murphy, Christina Murray,
Katherine O'Regan, Jeremy Sarkin, Henk Smith and Nico Steytler. Hugh Corder
subsequently became a member of the technical committee responsible for drafting
the interim Constitution's Bill of Rights, Katherine O'Regan became a Constitutional
Court judge, and Christina Murray became a member of the panel of experts
responsible for drafting the final Constitution.
[33] See id. at 13-67 (providing discussion of the Charter's provisions and
indicating the foreign influences on each provision).
[34] See DU PLESSIS & CORDER, supra note 31, at 48 (discussing the influences
behind the Bill of Right's "structure").
[35] See id. at 48-49.
[36] See Hugh Corder, Toward a South African Constitution, 57 MODERN L.R.
491, 514 (1994) (noting that these foreign models were useful because they
emphasized that rights should be expressed simply and broadly, while remaining
limitable and suspendable).
[37] See DU PLESSIS & CORDER, supra note 31, at 47-48.
[38] South Africa signed three major human rights treaties in 1994. These
were the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, Dec.
16, 1966, 993 U.N.T.S. 3, the International Covenant on Civil and Political
Rights, Dec. 16, 1966, 999 U.N.T.S. 171, and the International Convention
on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination, Dec. 21, 1965, 660
U.N.T.S. 195. Three documents were ratified by South Africa in 1995: the Convention
on the Rights of the Child, G. A. Res. 44/25, U.N. GAOR, 44th Sess., Supp.
No. 49, at 166, U.N. Doc. A/44/736 (1989); the Convention on the Elimination
of All Forms of Discrimination Against Women, G.A. Res. 34/180, U.N. GAOR,
34th Sess., Supp. No. 46, at 193, U.N. Doc. A/34/36 (1980); and the three
Protocols to the Geneva Convention. Parliament recommended ratification of
two more, the Convention Relating to the Status of Refugees, July 28, 1951,
189 U.N.T.S. 150, and the Convention Governing the Specific Aspects of Refugee
Problems in Africa, Sept. 10, 1969, 1001 U.N.T.S. 45. Although these latter
two documents were formally lodged in 1996, there has been little apparent
further movement on this front. Only two instruments were ratified in 1996:
The African Charter on Human and 'Peoples' Rights, Jun. 27, 1981, 21 I.L.M.
58, and the Convention relating to the Status of Refugees, July 28, 1951,
189 U.N.T.S. 150. It appears, however, that neither the administrative arm
of government nor Parliament has a strategy for reviewing international human
rights instruments or for determining whether to sign any others. 'Instruments
have been signed and ratified without adequate examination as to whether South
African law complies with them. Thus, reservations were not made and no review
has occurred which might identify laws that should be amended to bring them
into line with ratified international treaties and the Government does not
really understand South Africa's present obligations.
[39] S. AFR. CONST. of 1993 (IC), ch. 4, ?231(4); see also JOHN DUGARD, INTERNATIONAL
LAW: A SOUTH AFRICAN PERSPECTIVE 339-41 (1994) (discussing the relevance of
231(4)).
[40] Nduli and Another v. Minister of Justice and Others, 1978 (1) SALR 893,
898 (A).
[41] See S. AFR. CONST. of 1993 (IC), ch. 6, ?82(1)(i) ("The President
shall be competent to . . . negotiate and sign international agreements.");
see also S. AFR. CONST. of 1996, ch. 14, ?231(1) ("The negotiating and
signing of all international agreements is the responsibility of the national
executive.").
[42] See S. AFR. CONST. of 1993 (IC), ch. 15, ?231(2-3). Section 231(2) qualified
the President's power under Section 82(1)(i). See id. at ?231(2). Section
231(3) stated: "Where Parliament agrees to the ratification of or accession
to an international agreement under subsection (2), such international agreement
shall be binding on the Republic and shall form part of the law of the Republic,
provided Parliament expressly so provides and such agreement is not inconsistent
with this Constitution." Id. at 231(3).
[43] See id.
[44] Before 1993, South Africa was party only to the United Nations Charter.
It was only at the beginning of 1994 that South African signed a number of
conventions. These include the Convention on the Political Rights of Women,
July 7, 1954, 193 U.N.T.S. 135; the Convention on the Nationality of Married
Women, Feb. 20, 1957, 309 U.N.T.S. 65; the Recommendation on Consent to Marriage,
Minimum Age for Marriage and Registration of Marriages, G.A. Res. 2018, U.N.
GOAR, 20th Sess., Supp. No. 14, at 36, U.N. Doc. A/60141 (1965); the Convention
on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination Against Women, G.A. Res.
39/46, U.N. GAOR, 34th Sess., Supp. No. 46, at 193, U.N. Doc. A/34/46 (1980);
the Convention Against Torture and other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment
or Punishment, G.A. Res. 44/25, U.N. GAOR, 39th Sess., Supp. No. 51, at 197,
U.N. Doc A/39/51 (1985); and the Convention on the Rights of the Child, U.N.
GAOR, 44th Sess., Supp. No. 49, at 166, U.N. Doc. A/44/736 (1989).
[45] See Dermott J. Devine, The Relationship Between International Law and
Municipal Law in Light of the Interim South African Constitution Act '1993,
44 INT'L & COMP. L.Q. 1, 6-7 (Jan. 1995).
[46] See S. AFR. CONST. of 1996, ch. 14, ?231(2).
[47] See id. at ?231(4).
[48] See id.
[49] See id. at ch. 14, ?232.
[50] See id. at ch. 2, ?39(1)(b).
[51] See id. at ?39(1)(c).
[52] See DU PLESSIS & CORDER, supra note 31, at 40-41 (discussing extensively
the ideological debates between the minimalists and the optimists).
[53] See id.
[54] See id.
[55] See id. at 47.
[56] See id.
[57] See id.
[58] See id; AZAR CACHALIA, ET AL., FUNDAMENTAL RIGHTS IN THE NEW CONSTITUTION
24-32 (1994) (discussing Section 8).
[59] See DU PLESSIS & CORDER, supra note 31, at 47-48.
[60] See id. at 47.
[61] S. AFR. CONST. of 1993 (IC), ch. 3, ?35(1). Section 35(1) has been replaced
in the final Constitution by Section 39. See S. AFR. CONST. of 1996, ch. 2,
?39. Section 39 seems to strengthen the mandate to consider public law. The
section states that a court "must consider international law." Id.
at ?39(1)(b).
[62] See id.
[63] See John Dugard, `The Role of International Law in Interpreting the Bill
of 'Rights, 10 S. AFR. J. HUM. RTS. 208, 212 (1994).
[64] See id. at 212 (observing that "it is difficult to imagine situations
where public international law will not be applicable under 35(1)," of
the interim Constitution).
[65] See T. Vallinder, `The Judicialization of Politics: Meaning, Forms, Background,
Prospects', ACTA SOCIETATIS JURIDICAE LUNDENSIS `267 (1992) (providing a critically
important discussing of the reciprocal relationship between politics and the
judiciary); Cass R. Sunstein, Neutrality in Constitutional Law (with Special
Reference to Pornography, Abortion and '`Surrogacy), 92 COLUM. L. REV. 1 (1992)
(arguing that neutrality is a key principle in constitutional law and theory);
Peter H. Russell, The Political Purposes of the Canadian Charter of Rights
and '`Freedoms, 61 CAN. B. REV. 30 (1983); Alfred Hill, The Political Dimension
of Constitutional 'Adjudication, 63 S. CAL. L. REV. 1237 (1990).
[66] See Nic Haysom, `The Bill of Fundamental Rights: Implications For Legal
'Practice, DE REBUS 125, 128 (Feb. 1994).
[67] See DU PLESSIS & CORDER, supra note 31, at 47, 121.
[68] S. AFR. CONST. of 1993 (IC), ch. 3, ?35(2).
[69] See DU PLESSIS & CORDER, supra note 31, at 121.
[70] See id. at 123.
[71] See Catherine Albertyn & Janet Kentridge, `Introducing the Right
to Equality in the Interim Constitution,' 10 S. AFR. J. HUM. RTS. 149, 175
(1994) (observing that "[t]he inquiry under this section considers whether
incursions into the freedom from discrimination are permissible because they
serve a legitimate social purpose in a way which is proportionate to the end
which they seek to achieve").
[72] S. AFR. CONST of 1996 (IC), ch. 3, ?33(1).
[73] See DU PLESSIS & CORDER, supra note 31, at 123. Article 19(1) of
the German Basic Law states, "[i]n so far as a basic right may, under
the Basic Law, be restricted by or pursuant to a law. The law shall apply
generally and not merely to one case. Furthermore, the law shall specify the
basic right and relevant Article." GRUNDGESETZ [Constitution] [GG] art.
19(1) (F.R.G.) (Basic Law). The Basic Law was adopted by the parliamentary
council of West Germany in 1949, following World War II, in an attempt to
create a democratic political and social atmosphere.
[74] See CACHALIA, ET AL., supra note 58, at 115 (stating, however, that this
prevision of South Africa's interim Constitution is actually, "drawn
from article 19(1) of the German Basic Law [which] gives explicit recognition
to the fact that what is at stake . . . is legitimate circumscription of rights,
not their evisceration," which is reiterated by Section 19(2) of the
basic law).
[75] GRUNDGESETZ [Constitution] [GG] art. 19(1) (F.R.G.).
[76] CAN. CONST. (Constitution Act, 1982) pt. 1 (Canadian Charter of Rights
and Freedoms) ?1.
[77] Regina v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103.
[78] See id. at 135-40 (applying the limitations test and explaining its application).
[79] See id.
[80] See id. at 135 ("any ?1 inquiry much be premised on an understanding
that the impugned limit violates constitutional rights and freedoms").
[81] See id. at 136 (stating that the court should only allow exceptions to
the Charter's guarantees where the provision is "reasonably and demonstrably
justified" for a "free and democratic society").
[82] Id. at 139.
[83] See S. AFR. CONST. of 1993 (IC), ch. 3, ?33; see also CACHALIA, ET AL.,
supra note 58, at 105-16 (describing international case law that influenced
the construction of Section 33); DU PLESSIS & CORDER, supra note 31, at
122-33 (discussing limitation clause analysis).
[84] The Sunday Times Case, 30 EUR. CT. H.R. (ser. A.) 1 (1979).
[85] Id. at 31.
[86] S. AFR. CONST. of 1993 (IC), ch. 3, ?33(1)(a).
[87] P. VAN DIJK & G. J. H. VAN HOOF, THEORY AND PRACTICE OF THE EUROPEAN
CONVENTION OF HUMAN RIGHTS 583 (2nd ed. 1990).
[88] See Jeffrey Jowell & Anothony Lester, `Proportionality: Neither Novel
nor 'Dangerous, in NEW DIRECTIONS IN JUDICIAL REVIEW 51 (J.L. Jowell &
D. Oliver, eds. 1988) (discussing the role of proportionality in English law
through a historical analysis of proportionality in Europe); Harmut Gerstein
& David Lowry, Abortion, Abstract Norms, and Social Control: The Decision
of the West German Federal Constitutional Court, 25 EMORY L.J. 849 (1976)
(describing the Constitutional Court's application of the principle of "least
detrimental settlement" to preserve the central constitutional value
of human dignity in the context of abortion rights where individual rights--those
of the mother and fetus--compete).
[89] See id. at 53-54.
[90] See id. at 52-54 (defining the requirements for encroaching on individual
freedom).
[91] See Gerstein & Lowry, supra note 88, at 865.
[92] S. AFR. CONST. of 1993 (IC), ch. 3, ?33(1)(a)(iii).
[93] PAUL SIEGHART, THE INTERNATIONAL LAW OF HUMAN RIGHTS 93 (1983) (discussing
the European Court of Human Right's interpretation of the phrase, "necessary
in a democratic society," in Handyside v. United Kingdom, 24 EUR. CT.
H.R. (ser. A)).
[94] Handyside v. United Kingdom, 24 Eur. Ct. H.R. (ser. A.) (1976).
[95] See id. at 22.
[96] Id.; see also SIEGHART, supra note 93, at 66.
[97] See S. AFR. CONST. of 1993 (IC), ch. 3, ?33; id. at ?35; DU PLESSIS &
CORDER, supra note 31, at 126-27 (discussing the relationship between these
clauses and the application of the American strict scrutiny test despite the
limitation clauses roots in the Canadian and European constitutions).
[98] See DU PLESSIS & CORDER, supra note 31, at 127-28 (listing the rights
subject to strict scrutiny review).
[99] See Jeremy Gauntlett, Appointing and Promoting Judges: Which Way Now?
CONSULTUS (South Africa) 23 (1990) (on file with author); Jeremy Sarkin, `Judges
in South Africa: Black Sheep or Albino's?,' in 24 CENTRE FOR THE INDEPENDENCE
OF JUDGES AND LAWYERS BULLETIN (of the International Commission of Jurists)
(Geneva, Switzerland) 34, 37-38, 40-44 (1989) (on file with author) (questioning
whether judges' roles in perpetuating an unjust and illegitimate system has
tainted the credibility or that the good they can now do justifies their remaining
on the bench).
[100] See Jeremy Sarkin, The Political Role of the South African Constitutional
Court, 114 S. AFR. L.J. 134, 134-36 (1997) (considering the extent to which
political parties may use Court to fight their political battles); G. Barrie,
`The Challenge of the South African Judiciary in the 1990s' TYDSKRIF VAN SUID
AFRIKAANSE REG 515 (1989) (on file with author).
[101] See D.D. Mokgatle, `The Exclusion of Blacks from the South African Judicial
System', 3 S. AFR. J. HUM. RTS. 44, 45-46 (1987). The first person of color
to sit on the Supreme Court was Hassan E. Mall, who was an acting judge for
one month in 1987. See Michael Parks, South Africa Names First Non-While to
Judicial Post, L.A. TIMES, Jan. 18, 1987, at 8. In August of 1991, Mr. Ismail
Mahomed became the first person of color appointed full time to the Supreme
Court bench. See First Black Appointed to South Africa Supreme Court to Speak
at Penn, LEGAL INTELLIGENCER, Jan. 23, 1992, at 2.
[102] See Parliament of South Africa, Hansard, 28 Apr. 1989 cols. 7097-98.
[103] See Charles R.M. Dlamini, `The Influence of Race on the Administration
of Justice in South Africa', 4 S. AFR. J. HUM. RTS. 37, 53-54 (1988) (arguing
that blacks distrusted the system in part because of its white composition).
[104] See David Beatty, The Rule (and Role) of Law in New South Africa; Some
Lessons Learned From Abroad, 109 S. AFR. L.J. 408, 422 (1992).
[105] See DU PLESSIS & CORDER, supra note 31, at 67.
[106] Id., at 67-72 (describing in brief the establishment of a criticism
of the South African judiciary as an scholarly discipline in South Africa
and the major theories of criticism.).
[107] See SA LAW COMMISSION, 3 CONSTITUTIONAL MODELS (PROJECT 77) 1200-01.
[108] The full Association of Law Societies proposal is reprinted in `ALS
Proposes New Legal Dispensation for South Africa' 1990 DE REBUS 587.
[109] See id.
[110] The Conference on a Constitutional Court took place in 1991 with a range
of international speakers evaluating different court models. See V. Moreina,
`The Portuguese Constitutional Court,' (1991) (paper delivered at the Conference
on a Constitutional Court) `(on file with author); see also Kader Asmal, Constitutional
Courts - A Comparative Survey', 24 COMP. & INT'L L.J. S. AFR. 315, 337-40
(1991); J. Van der Westhuizen, `The Protection of Human Rights and a Constitutional
Court for South Africa: Some Questions and Ideas, With Reference to the German
Experience', DE JURE 1 (1991) (on file with author).
[111] See Johan D. van der Vyver, The Randolph W. Thrower Symposium, Comparative
Constitutionalism: Constitutional Optionxs for Post-Apartheid South Africa,
40 EMORY L.J. 745, 802-4 (1991) (discussing proposals for a constitutional
court and the arguments made in support of different structures).
[112] See Arthur Chaskalson, `A Constitutional Court: Jurisdiction, Possible
Models and Questions of Access,' 95 (1991) (paper delivered at the Constitutional
Court Conference) (on file with author).
[113] See Haysom, The Bill of Fundamental Rights, supra note 66, at 126.
[114] See Sarkin, supra note 100, at 134. But see M.G. Cowling, Judges and
the Protection of Human Rights in South Africa: Articulating the Inarticulate
Premiss, 3 S. AFR. J. HUM. RTS. 177, 195 (1987).
[115] See van der Vyver, supra note 111, at 802 (reviewing the views of the
Olivier Commission and the African National Congress); see generally DU PLESSIS
& CORDER, supra note 31, at 191-200 (discussing the proposals for the
enforcement mechanisms needed to protect the fundamental rights provided in
the interim Constitution).
[116] See van der Vyver, supra note 111, at 802.
[117] See id.
[118] See S. AFR. CONST. of 1993 (IC), ch. 7, ?98.
[119] Id. at ch. 7, ?101.
[120] See S. AFR. CONST of 1996, ch. 8, Ё 168, 169.
[121] See id. at ?167(5). Section 167(5) states, "The Constitutional
Court makes the final decision whether an Act of Parliament, a provincial
Act or conduct of the President is constitutional, and must confirm to any
order of invalidity made by the Supreme Court of Appeal, a High Court, or
a court of similar status, before that order has any force." Id.
[122] See S. AFR. CONST. of 1993 (IC), ch. 7, ?99.
[123] See LAWRENCE BAUM, THE SUPREME COURT 30-60 (6th ed. 1998) (reviewing
the selection process of the United States Supreme Court justices).
[124] See id. at ?98(1) ("There shall be a Constitutional Court consisting
of a President and 10 other judges appointed in terms of Section 99.").
[125] See id. at ?99(1) ("[T]he judges of the Constitutional Court shall
be appointed by the President for a non-renewable period of seven years.").
[126] See id. at ?99(2)(a) ("No person shall be qualified to be appointed
President or a judge of the Constitutional Court unless he or she - (a) is
a South African cititzen.").
[127] Id. at ?99(2)(b) ("No person shall be qualified to be appointed
President or a judge of the Constitutional Court unless he or she . . . (b)
is a fit and proper person to be a judge of the Constitutional Court.").
[128] See id. at ?99(2)(c)(i). This section requires that a candidate "is
a judge of the Supreme Court or is qualified to be admitted as an advocate
or attorney and has, for a cumulative period of at least 10 years after having
so qualified, practiced as an advocate or an attorney or lectured in law at
a university." Id.
[129] See id. at ?99(2)(c)(ii). Section 99(2)(c)(ii) allows for a Justice
to be "a person who, by reason of his or her training and experience,
has expertise in the field of constitutional law relevant to the application
of this Constitution and the law of the Republic." Id.
[130] See id. at ?99(4).
[131] Id. at ?97(2)(a).
[132] See id. at ?99(6).
[133] Id.
[134] S. AFR. CONST. of 1993 (IC), ch. 7, ?99(3). These judges were: Laurie
Ackerman, judge of the Cape Provincial Division and formerly Professor of
Human Rights at the University of Stellenbosch, Ismail Mohammed, judge of
the Transvaal Provincial Division, Richard Goldstone, judge of the Apellate
Division and chairperson of the Goldstone Commission, and Thole Madala of
the Transkei Supreme Court. See Patrick Lawrence & Gail Irwin, Watchdogs
of the Constitution, STAR (South Africa), Feb. 13, 1995, at 13.
[135] S. AFR. CONST. of 1993 (IC), ch. 7, ?99(4).
[136] See id. at ?99(5)(a) ("In respect of the first appointment after
the commencement of the Constitution of the six judges referred to in subsection
(4), the Judicial Service Commission shall submit a list of ten nominees.").
[137] See id. at ?99(5)(b) ("If the appointing authorities decide not
to accept any or some of such recommendations, the Judicial Service Commission
shall be informed thereof and be furnished with reasons therefore.").
[138] See id. at ?99(5)(c) ("After having been informed in terms of paragraph
(b), the Judicial Service Commission shall, in accordance with paragraph (a),
submit further recommendations, whereafter the appointing authorities shall
make the appointment or appointments from the recommendations as supplemented
in terms of this paragraph.").
[139] See id. at ?105(1).
[140] See Beatty, supra note 104, at 425 (1992) (explaining that the Judicial
Services Commission in South Africa "tend[s] to be dominated (either
numerically or interpersonally or both) by senior members of the judiciary
and the legal profession--the two groups with the strongest connections and
(psychological) commitments to the past").
[141] See Lawrence & Irwin, supra note 134, at 13 (providing biographical
information about each of the eleven justices). But cf. Bob Drogin, 11 Activist
Sworn in for News S. African Court, L.A. TIMES, Feb. 15, 1995, at A8 (noting
that some "critics have called the new court too white, too male and
too stacked with partisans of the ANC").
[142] See Drogin, supra note 141, at A8.
[143] Since the Constitutional Court first convened, it has decided most of
its cases without dissent. See, e.g., State v. Makwanyane, 1995 (3) SALR 391
(CC) (containing 10 concurring opinions).
[144] See infra notes 189-200 and text accompanying.
[145] See Makwanyane, 1995 (3) SALR 391 (holding that capital punishment violates
the right to life, dignity, and to be free from cruel, inhuman or degrading
punishment guaranteed by the South African constitution).
[146] See State v. Williams and Another, 1995(3) SALR 632 (CC) (holding that
juvenile corporal punishment violates various sections of the interim Constitution).
[147] See Coetzee v. Government of the Republic of South Africa; Matiso and
Others v. Commanding Officer, Port Elizabeth Prisons and Others, 1995 (4)
SALR 631 (CC) (holding that the imprisonment of debtors might violate the
Constitution); Danie Olivier, Civil Imprisonment Held To Be Unconstitutional?,
DE REBUS, Nov. 1995, at 701 (discussing Coetzee).
[148] See Shabalala and Others v. Attorney-General of Transvaal and Another,
1996 (1) SALR 725 (CC) (finding that the interim Constitution contained the
right for defendants to access police dockets and witnesses); Danie Olivier,
Recent Constitutional Cases, DE REBUS, Jan. 1996, at 35-36 (discussing Shabalala).
[149] See In re The School Education Bill of 1995 (Gauteng), 1996 (3) SALR
165 (CC) (upholding disputed sections of the School Education Bill of 1995
relating to the use of language and religion to segregate schools); Nel v.
Le Roux, 1996 (3) SALR 562 (CC); Case and Another v. Minister of Safety and
Security and Others; Curtis v. Minister of Safety and Security and Others,
1996 (3) SALR 617 (CC); Du Plessis and Another v. De Klerk, 1996 (3) SALR
850 (CC); Besserglik v. Minister of Trade, Industry and Tourism, 1996 (4)
SALR 331 (CC) (holding that leave to appeal is constitutional); Brink v. Kitshoff,
1996 (4) SALR 197 (CC) (affirming right to equality before the law).
[150] See Case and Another v. Minister of Safety and Security and Others;
Curtis v. Minister of Safety and Security and Others, 1996 (3) SALR 617 (CC);
Du Plessis and Another v. De Klerk, 1996 (3) SALR 850 (CC); Key v. Attorney-General,
Cape of Good Hope, 1996 (4) SALR 187 (CC) (defining a "fairness standard"
for the admission of evidence obtained by search and seizure); Bernstein and
Others v. Bester NO and Others, 1996 (2) SALR 751 (CC); Rudolph and Another
v. Commissioner for Inland Revenue, 1996 (4) SALR 552 (CC) (holding that the
interim Constitution does not apply to search and seizure issues arising before
the constitution came into force); In re: Kwazulu-Natal Amakhosi and Iziphakanyewa
Amendment Bill of 1995; In re: Payment of Salaries and Other Privileges to
Ingonyama Bill of 1995, 1996 (4) SALR 653 (CC) (holding that bills prohibiting
or limiting remuneration of traditional leaders to those required by provincial
law or custom do not violate the constitution).
[151] See Case and Another v. Minister of Safety and Security and Others;
Curtis v. Minister of Safety and Security and Others, 1996 (3) SALR 617 (CC);
Du Plessis and Another v. De Klerk (3) SALR 850 (CC); Gardener v. Whitaker,
1996 (4) SALR 337 (CC); Bernstein and Others v. Bester NO and Others, 1996
(2) SALR 751 (CC); In re: Kwazulu-Natal Amakhosi and Iziphakanyewa Amendment
Bill of 1995; In re: Payment of Salaries and Other Privileges to Ingonyama
Bill of 1995, 1996 (7) BCLR 903 (CC).
[152] See Executive Council of the Western Cape Legislature and Others v.
President of the Republic of South Africa and Others, 1995 (4) SALR 877 (CC)
(clarifying the boundaries of central and provincial government authority);
In re: Kwazul-Natal Amakhosi and Iziphakanyewa Amendment Bill of 1995; In
re: Payment of Salaries and Other Privileges to Ingonyama Bill of 1995, 1996
(6) BCLR 903 (CC); Education: In re: School Education Bill off 1995 (Gauteng)
1996 (3) SALR 617 (CC); In re: National Education Policy Bill No 82 of 1995
1996 (4) BCLR 518 (CC).
[153] See, e.g., du Plessis and Another v. De Klerk, 1996 (3) SALR 850 (CC).
[154] See, e.g., Claydon & Hatfield, supra note 8, at 354-59 (discussing
the use of international sources to interpret the Canadian Bill of Rights,
which like the South African Bill of Rights, was influenced in its construction
by external legal sources).
[155] See id. at 354-55.
[156] 1995 (3) SALR 391 (CC).
[157] See id; see generally Jeremy Sarkin, `Problems and Challenges Facing
South Africa's Constitutional Court: An Evaluation of its Decisions on Capital
and Corporal Punishment,' 113 S. AFR. L.J. 71 (1996) (discussing the Constitutional
Court's opinions in Makwanyane and State v. Williams & Others, 1995 (3)
SALR 632 (CC)); P.M. Maduna, The Death Penalty and Human Rights, 12 S. AFR.
J. HUM. RTS. 193 (1996) (providing a detailed discussion of the Makwanyane
decision and its social context); `'G .Carpenter, `Constitutional Court Sounds
the Death Knell for Capital Punishment,' 59 TYDSKRIF VIR HEDENDAAGSE ROMEINS-HOLLANDSE
REG 145 (1996) (on file with author); J Milton, Demise of the Death Penalty:
The Constitutional Court Pronounces, 8 S. AFR. J. CRIM. JUST. 188-204 (1995).`'
[158] See Makwanyane, 1995 (3) SALR at 391.
[159] It is still possible for the death penalty to be imposed where an individual
is convicted for treason while South Africa is at war.
[160] See Makwanyane, 1995 (3) SALR at 401-53.
[161] Id. at 451; see also S. AFR. CONST. of 1993 (IC), ch. 3, ?11(2).
[162] Makwanyane, 1995 (3) SALR at 429-32; see also S. AFR. CONST. of 1993
(IC), ch. 3, ?9.
[163] Makwanyane, 1995 (3) SALR at 422-24; see also S. AFR. CONST. of 1993
(IC), ch. 3, ?10.
[164] See Makwanyane, 1995 (3) SALR at 417-22.
[165] See id. at 425-27.
[166] Id. at 414.
[167] See id.
[168] Park-Ross v. Director, Office of Serious Economic Offenses, 1995 (2)
SALR 148, 160 (CC).
[169] See In re Gauteng Education Bill of 1995, 1996 (3) SALR 165 (CC).
[170] See id. at 170-71.
[171] See id.
[172] See id. at 175-76 (distinguishing Section 32(C) of the interim Constitution
from Section 23 of the Canadian Charter because the Canadian Charter places
an explicit affirmative duty on the Canadian Government to provide education
in both English and French).
[173] See id. at 186 n.6, 190-208 (Sachs, J., concurring).
[174] See id. at 190-97.
[175] Id. at 206.
[176] Id.
[177] See Azanian Peoples Organization (AZAPO) and Others v. President of
the Republic of South Africa and Others, 1996 (4) SALR 671 (CC); see generally
Jeremy Sarkin, `The Trials and Tribulations of the South African Truth and
Reconciliation Commission,' 12 S. AFR. J. HUM. RTS. 617 (1996); Jeremy Sarkin,
`The Truth and Reconciliation Commission in South Africa," COMM. L. BULL.
(1997).
[178] Parliament enacted the Promotion of National Unity and Reconciliation
Act in 1995 pursuant to the authority contained in the epilogue of the interim
Constitution. See AZAPO, 1996 (4) SALR at 677; see also S. AFR. CONST. of
1993. The commission was conceived as a method of healing the wounds of apartheid.
See AZAPO, 1996 (4) SALR at 677, 684.
[179] S. AFR. CONST. of 1993 (IC), ch. 3, 22(1).
[180] See AZAPO, 1996 (4) SALR at 687-88.
[181] Deputy President Mahomed wrote the main opinion. Justices Chaskalson,
Ackermann, Kriegler, Langa, Madala, Mokgoro, O'Regan and Sachs concurred.
Justice Didcott agreed with the findings of Justice Mahomed but wrote separately.
[182] For an evaluation of the most important prosecution for human rights
abuses `committed, see Howard Varney & Jeremy Sarkin, Failing to Pierce
the Hit Squad Veil: An Analysis of the Malan 'Trial, 10 S. AFR. J. CRIM. J.
141 (1997).
[183] See AZAPO, 1996 (4) SALR at 681.
[184] See id. at 682-83. The Court explained that the epilogue gave Parliament
the power to grant amnesty. See id. Section 33(1) allows laws of general application
to limit rights granted by the interim Constitution as long as the law does
not negate the "essential content" of the right and is reasonable,
justified and, depending on the right in question, necessary. See S. AFR.
CONST. of 1993 (IC), ch. 3, ?33(1).
[185] AZAPO, 1996 (4) SALR at 684.
[186] Id. at 682-83.
[187] Id. at 686.
[188] See id. at 686-87 (discussing the countries of Chile, Argentina and
El Salvador which also formed truth commissions to help repair the damage
created by a history of subjugation).
[189] See id. at 688-89. The Court supported this argument with reference
to Section 231 of the interim Constitution. See id.
[190] Id. at 686.
[191] See id. at 690 (discussing article 6(5) of the Protocol II of the Geneva
Convention of 1949).
[192] Id. at 689-90.
[193] See id. at 692-93 (defining amnesty and its Greek origin as being an
"act of oblivion").
[194] Id. at 693.
[195] See id. at 694-95 ("The resources of the State have to deployed
imaginatively, wisely, efficiently, and equitably to facilitate the reconstruction
process.").
[196] See, e.g., Executive Council, Western Cape Legislature v. Presidents
of the Republic of South Africa, 1995 (4) SALR 877, 904-905 (CC) (allowing
Parliament to take action without following Constitutional procedures in exceptional
circumstances); Premier, Kwazulu-Natal v. President of the Republic of South
Africa, 1996 (1) SALR 769, 783-84 (CC) (establishing a liberal check on constitutional
amendments); Sarkin,`' supra note100, at 149-50 (discussing the Court's deference
to Parliament regarding policy determinations which allows Parliament to "govern
with very little judicial interference").
[197] The interim Constitution mandated that the Constitutional Court determine
the validity of the final Constitution. See S. AFR. CONST. of 1993 (IC), ch.
5, ?71(2). The Court had to determine whether the text fell within the political
pact negotiated before the 1994 elections and recorded in thirty-four constitutional
principles in the interim Constitution. Once again, the Court interpreted
its brief narrowly, displaying a reluctance to be seen as interfering with
and upsetting a carefully crafted political compromise. See Ex parte Chairperson
of the Constitutional Assembly; In re Certification of the Constitution of
the Republic of South Africa, 1996 (4) SALR 744 (CC) (noting that the judicial
certification of the Constitution was unprecedented). Its ruling determining
the constitutionality of the KwaZulu-Natal Constitution was more bold, with
the Court emphatically declaring that the text might be seen as an attempt
by the province to usurp more power than it was granted under the interim
Constitution. See Certification of the Amended Text of the Constitution of
the Republic of South Africa 1996, 1997 (2) SALR 97, 162 (CC).
[198] See, e.g., State v. Vermaas; State v. du Plessis, 1995 (3) SALR 292
(CC); Jeremy Sarkin, The Constitutional Court's Decision on Legal Representation:
State v. Vermaas; State v. du Plessis, 12 S. AFR. J. HUM. RTS. 55 (1996);
Jeremy Sarkin, Problems and Challenges Facing South Africa's Constitutional
Court: An Evaluation of its Decisions on Capital and Corporal Punishment,
113 S. AFR. L.J. 71 (1996).
[199] AZAPO, 1996 (4) SALR at 695.
[200] Id. at 698.
[201] See PETER W. HOGG, CONSTITUTIONAL LAW OF CANADA 653 (1985).
[202] Id. at 646.
[203] See JOHAN BRIGHAM, CONSTITUTIONAL LANGUAGE: AN INTERPRETATION OF JUDICIAL
DECISION 58 (1978).