公 法 评 论 | 惟愿公平如大水滚滚,使公义如江河滔滔 et revelabitur quasi aqua iudicium et iustitia quasi torrens fortis |
MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
1945
MODUS VIVENDI POSTMODERNUS
?ON
JUST INTERPRETATIONSAND THE THINNING OF JUSTICE
Frank I. Michelman
For all its multiculturalist sympathies and flippable title,
Michel Rosenfeld’s
Just Interpretations1 has no truck with anypostmodern loss of faith or withdrawal from strongly prescriptive
talk about justice in law.2 A formidable work of straight normative
political theory, the book acutely and elegantly restates a central
problem in the moral justification of political practice, canvasses
responses proposed by various eminent doctors, finds all of them
wanting, and ends by offering its own duly chastened response.
Just Interpretations
joins a quite specifically identifiabledebate. The question is whether and how we may have liberal
legitimacy in democratic politics.3 As John Rawls puts the
question: “[I]n the light of what principles and ideals must we, as
free and equal citizens, be able to view ourselves as exercising [our
power as a collective body] if our exercise of [this power] is to be
justifiable to other citizens and to respect their being reasonable
and rational?”4 In other words: Given a general, prima facie moral
objection to coercion, what sort of guiding criteria for laws and
their applications might possibly justify the coercive practice of
democratic politics?5
??
Robert Walmlsey University Professor, Harvard University.1 MICHEL ROSENFELD, JUST INTERPRETATIONS: LAW BETWEEN ETHICS AND
POLITICS (1998).
2
See DUNCAN KENNEDY, A CRITIQUE OF ADJUDICATION (FIN DE SIèCLE) 8, 311-12 (1997) (“loss of faith”); Pierre Schlag,
Normative and Nowhere to Go, 43 STAN. L. REV.167, 171, 177 (1990).
3
See Frank I. Michelman, Morality, Identity, and Constitutional Patriotism, 76 DENV.U. L. REV. 1009, 1009-10, 1014-18 (1999) (analyzing political-justificational aims of
contemporary liberal political philosophy).
4 JOHN RAWLS, POLITICAL LIBERALISM 136 (2d ed. 1996).
5 Rosenfeld rightly includes all episodes of lawmaking and law application under the
head of legal “interpretation.” ROSENFELD,
supra note 1, at 2 (“For justice to beachieved . . . requires just interpretations of applicable laws and . . . laws that are
themselves the product of just interpretations.”);
see also FRANK I. MICHELMAN,BRENNAN AND DEMOCRACY ch. 1 (1999); Frank I. Michelman,
ConstitutionalAuthorship
, in CONSTITUTIONALISM: PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS 64 (LarryAlexander ed., 1998); Frank I. Michelman,
Always Under Law?, 12 CONST. COMM. 227MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
1946
CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 21:1945Various answers are proposed. Jürgen Habermas, for
example, offers a “democratic principle,” drawn from discourse
theory, to the effect that morally legitimate laws are those able to
gain the assent of everyone in a legally guaranteed, democratically
constituted, “discursive process” of “opinion and will-formation.”6
Rawls himself offers the idea of a “political conception of justice,”
a substantive doctrine of political rightness developed from ideal
notions, including a basic norm of reciprocity, that he finds already
resident in constitutional-democratic public culture.7 Michel
Rosenfeld proposes, instead, a substantive doctrine of the good he
calls “comprehensive pluralism.” Among my specific aims in this
review is to understand precisely how Rosenfeld means his
proposal to differ from that of Rawls.
Initially, I grant, there is little mystery about that. Rosenfeld
pointedly places the ethic of comprehensive pluralism, a
conception of
goodness, on a plane of direct competition with bothHabermasian procedural and Rawlsian substantive conceptions of
rightness
, as the best available guide to the justification of politicalcoercion.8 “[T]o the extent that comprehensive pluralism amounts
to yet another conception of the good,” he writes in what I shall be
treating as a key passage:
[I]t is clearly distinguishable from contemporary Kantian
visions such as those of Habermas or of Rawls in
A Theory ofJustice
. On the other hand, to the extent that comprehensivepluralism is more than yet another conception of the good, in
that it unleashes an inevitable but ultimately resolvable dialectic
between first-order and second-order norms, it differs markedly
from theories based on building an “overlapping consensus,”
such as that elaborated by Rawls in
Political Liberalism, andfrom all theories ultimately reducible to mere relativism.9
The meaning of this passage is not immediately and transparently
evident. To understand it fully, I shall suggest, is to peer deep into
Rosenfeld’s thoughts about the form of any possible answer to the
problem of liberal legitimacy in politics.
(1995).
6 JüRGEN HABERMAS, BETWEEN FACTS AND NORMS: CONTRIBUTIONS TO A
DISCOURSE THEORY OF LAW AND DEMOCRACY 110 (William Rehg trans., 1996).
7
See infra text accompanying notes 45-48; see also RAWLS, supra note 4; Frank I.Michelman,
Rawls on Constitutionalism and Constitutional Law, in THE CAMBRIDGECOMPANION TO JOHN RAWLS (Samuel Freeman ed., forthcoming 2000) (describing
Rawlsian idea of a political conception of justice); John Rawls,
The Idea of Public ReasonRevisited
, in COLLECTED PAPERS 573 (Samuel Freeman ed., 1999).8 On the conceptual opposition of rightness and goodness, see
infra textaccompanying notes 59-60.
9 ROSENFELD,
supra note 1, at 201.MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
2000]
POSTMODERN JUST INTERPETATIONS 1947I. WHAT CRISIS?
A.
The Crisis ConstructedJust Interpretations
begins by depicting a crisis-a crisis for us,here and now. Let us say, to keep things simple, that it’s a crisis
for contemporary Americans (although not for them alone).
Called a crisis of legal interpretation, is it also plainly to be
understood as a crisis of justice and political legitimacy. In
retracing the way in which Rosenfeld sets up the crisis, I shall use
the same terminology that he has used in his book. I warn the
reader, though, that what follows is an
interpretation, not arepetition, of Rosenfeld’s text. Whether it is a just interpretation,
or rather is just an interpretation, will not be for me to say.
Rosenfeld divides all politically governed societies or
“polities” into the two classes of the “homogeneous” and the
“heterogeneous.” He subdivides heterogeneous polities into the
two subclasses of “modern” and “postmodern.” Rosenfeld
attributes the crisis to the most historically recent quadrant of this
society/polity space-time-that of the postmodern subtype of the
heterogeneous polities.
There is no crisis in homogeneous polities because these are
defined as polities in which ethical and ideological consensus over
ideas of the good and dominant common interests is so wide, deep,
and strong as to leave little or no dispute over the guiding criteria
for just legal interpretations.10 Even in such societies, Rosenfeld
expects, there must inevitably be some disagreement over
decisions of specific cases, but that disagreement will be swamped
in a widespread sense of confidence that all are applying the same
system of ethical and ideological commitments, the same
conceptions of what gives value to human life and what is in the
overriding common interest of society.
Heterogeneous polities, incontrast, are those in which the depth of the differences among
numerous thriving and conflicting ethical value systems and
ideological formations precludes any sense of rooted agreement on
10
See id. at 2. Rosenfeld focuses mainly on ethical divisions, or those over ideas of thegood, referring only occasionally to what I would call ideological divisions, or those over
dominant common interests-a salient example of which would be conflicts between the
outlooks of owners and workers in at least some forms of capitalism. Rosenfeld uses the
term “ideological” in a slightly different way, describing “labor” and “management” as
possibly sharing a “capitalist ideology,” even while holding differing “perspectives” within
it.
Id. at 204-05. He would not quarrel, however, with the view that both dimensions ofdifference are relevant to his diagnosis of a current crisis of legal interpretation.
Accordingly, I will often speak, in what follows, of “ethical and ideological” divisions and
conflicts. My notion of ideological conflict here follows that in KENNEDY,
supra note 2, at41.
MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
1948
CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 21:1945guiding substantive criteria for justice in legal interpretations,
much less on the justice of every interpretation actually reached
and applied by officials and citizens.11
Not every heterogeneous polity, however, is caught in the
crisis, because ethically and ideologically rooted agreement-
“substantive” agreement-is not the only kind of agreement we
might have on the justice of legal interpretations. Among
heterogeneous polities-those in which substantive agreement on
justice in law is impossible-some fall into the class of what
Rosenfeld calls modern polities.12 In such a polity, despite the
presence of an irreconcilable plurality of conflicting conceptions of
the good and of the common interest, there nevertheless can be
found a widely shared understanding about how to bridge the
resulting fissures so as to maintain social unity and coherence.
This shared understanding takes the form of a largely
proceduralized conception of justice, an agreement that justice is
largely a matter of the observance of institutional arrangements
and procedures that mediate appropriately among ethical value
systems and ideological claims. What people in a modern polity
manage to retain, if only barely, as Rosenfeld beautifully
explains-what gives them their social unity and cohesion-is a
somewhat precarious (“contingent”) sense of confidence that their
basic institutional setups really do effectuate a suitable division of
labor among the normative domains of law, ethics, and politics.13
A postmodern polity, in contrast, not only lacks any unity or
convergence on ethical values and common interests, but further
lacks any “broadly based shared understanding” of how to
maintain social unity while at the same time “preserving . . .
plurality and dealing fairly with the issues that arise as a
consequence of . . . diversity.”14 In other words, in a postmodern
polity, there is lacking not only a substantive, but also a
procedural, consensus. As Rosenfeld puts the case, not only have
“commonly held norms and values reced[ed] nearly completely,”
but also we have come to the point where every possible
“institutional means” for regulating conflicts among competing
conceptions of the good seems biased in favor of some substantive
competitors.15 So deep and sharp have our ethical and ideological
divisions become that it seems we no longer can make
any lawstouching these divisions that are sufficiently determinate to hold
11
See ROSENFELD, supra note 1, at 2-3.12
Id. at 3-6.13
Id. at 5.14
Id. at 6.15
Id. at 7.MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
2000]
POSTMODERN JUST INTERPETATIONS 1949off unjust arbitrariness at the stage of applying them, without
introducing unjust partiality at the point of framing them. All
interpretations, then-all acts of political authority taken in the
name of the law-must be unjust (or at any rate cannot be known
or seen to be just), either because the laws and principles that
constrain them are unjust or because they are not credibly
constrained by any laws and principles.16 And that, then, is the
crisis from which Rosenfeld believes we now stand in need of
relief, in the form of a new-minted understanding of how law can
bridge the gap between self and other.
B.
The Crisis Deconstructed?Rosenfeld’s ideal-typical classification of polities depends
crucially on a distinction he draws between two kinds of
disagreement about justice in legal interpretations. Obviously,
there can be disagreement over the prescriptive content of the idea
of justice, or what Rosenfeld calls the “normative criteria” to be
used in appraising the conformity to justice of any given
interpretation. But even when people are sure they agree about
those criteria, or what we would call the standards or principles of
justice, Rosenfeld says they can disagree about whether a given
instance of interpretation satisfies justice.17 In Rosenfeld’s view,
the problem of just legal interpretations is solved only when both
kinds of disagreement are adequately held in check. A society in
which too many legal interpretations are found unjust by too many
citizens or groups is, in his apparent view, ipso facto not a justly
governed society. In other words-and this is a point to bear in
mind-there is, in Rosenfeld’s apparent view, an internal
connection between the prevalence or non-prevalence of justice in
a given polity and the social distribution of belief in the justness of
the legal interpretations in that polity
16
Cf. id. at 4-5 (discussing stresses in “modern” polities).17 I speak, as does Rosenfeld, of the justice (unmodified) of legal interpretations,
rather than specifically of the
legal justice of legal interpretations. Rosenfeld doesdifferentiate “justice according to law” from “justice beyond law.”
See, e.g., id. at 89. Buthe does so only for analytical purposes and without ever implying that justice in legal
interpretations can finally be severed from justice
simpliciter. See, e.g., id. at 55. “[J]usticein the context of law,” he writes, “cannot be legitimately confined to justice according to
law.”
Id. This is not to deny that justice in legal interpretation is legal justice (perhapsamong other things), evincing due regard for positive law as it really is. It is, rather, to
subsume the doing of legal justice under the doing of justice. We assume, in other words,
that legal officials do not act justly at all if they fail to give due consideration to the
requirements of legal justice-meaning, by due consideration, whatever consideration
justice unmodified requires. The open question is: What and how can the idea of legal
justice-official decision and action according to law-contribute toward the achievement
of justice, or at least the reduction of injustice?
MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
1950
CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 21:1945We must notice, now, that when Rosenfeld speaks of people
agreeing on the standards or criteria of justice but reaching
differing conclusions about what those criteria require in specific
cases, he is not just observing that people can disagree about the
specific facts of the cases before them, regarding the relevant
immediate acts and relations of the parties. He means they can
also disagree over how to apply an agreed measure of justice to the
decision of a case where the adjudicative facts-as legal theorists
would call them-are transparently clear and undisputed. For
example, the agreed standard might be a ban on laws prohibiting
the free exercise of religion and the case might be one of an Air
Force officer punished for (admittedly) having worn a yarmulke
while on duty, in (admittedly) direct and flagrant violation of an
(admittedly) duly promulgated military regulation.18
People, Rosenfeld says, can agree on the “free exercise”
standard-and be confident they are agreed on something very
important-even as they obdurately disagree over application of
the standard to a specific case. It thus seems that, in Rosenfeld’s
view, a normative standard can at least sometimes retain its
identity-can be held constant-under mutually contradictory
applications. People, in his apparent view, can at least sometimes
retain their certainty that they are all applying the same criterion
of judgment, even while they disagree about what result that
criterion requires in a case in which there is no dispute about how
to describe the relevant immediate facts. This decoupling of the
identity of a normative principle from its applications is an
absolutely crucial point for Rosenfeld. On it depends his
construction of the crisis.
For consider: If every disagreement about how to decide a
factually undisputed case in accordance with justice were taken to
disclose a hitherto latent disagreement about the applicable
principles or criteria of justice “themselves,” that would be the end
of the Rosenfeldian distinction between homogeneous and
heterogeneous polities. Without the idea that people can maintain
their sense of agreement on one and the same normative principle
even as they disagree diametrically over how to apply it, we would
never be able to say, as Rosenfeld says of homogeneous polities,
that there is constant agreement on the principles, even given the
inevitable disagreement about their applications. And yet there
appears to be a problem with putting the matter this way, for it
seems the very same thing could be said of our society.
In American society, for example, there is constant agreement
18
Cf. Goldman v. Weinberger, 475 U.S. 503 (1986).MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
2000]
POSTMODERN JUST INTERPETATIONS 1951on the abstract principle of free exercise of religion, accompanied
by deep and chronic disagreement about the application of this
principle to cases such as that of the Air Force captain and his
yarmulke. There is constant agreement on the abstract principle
of equality of governmental concern and respect for every person,
accompanied by deep and chronic disagreement about the
application of this principle to decide questions about whether
government in the United States today is required to be
colorblind, or rather is sometimes permitted, or even required, to
act in a race-conscious manner.19 Generalizing from these
examples, can it not be said of us that we have a consensus on
substantive political values, provided only that we state these
values at a high enough level of abstraction from hot controversy,
whether ethically or ideologically fueled? Can it not be said of us
that our disagreements occur only on the level of applying our
agreed principles to particular controversies? If so, then how are
we Americans not, by Rosenfeld’s definition, a homogeneous
society?
Of course, Rosenfeld cannot tolerate any such inference, for
its plain result would be that the crisis he constructs has no
application to us. (And if not to us, then to whom?) And so we
have before us a question about how Rosenfeld can avoid this
inference that appears to be fatal for his project of prescribing for
a crisis.
Perhaps he could say that Americans imagine they agree on
basic normative principles of political justice when they really do
not. If we Americans lack even near-agreement on the application
of our “equality” principle to decision of the color-blindnessversus-
race-consciousness question, or on the application of our
religious-freedom principle to broadly applicable regulatory laws
that severely and exceptionally impede particular, minority
religious observances,20 or of our proprietary-liberty principle to
onerous workplace and environmental regulation,21 then what is it
in those general neighborhoods of normative concern that we have
got agreement
on? Rosenfeld might answer: nothing that mattersto the purpose at hand, nothing that averts the crisis. But that
would be a leap from the pan to the fire. It would be, in effect, to
assert that disagreement over the application of a normative
19
See MICHEL ROSENFELD, AFFIRMATIVE ACTION AND JUSTICE: APHILOSOPHICAL AND CONSTITUTIONAL INQUIRY (1991).
20
See City of Boerne v. Flores, 521 U.S. 507 (1997); Employment Div. v. Smith, 494U.S. 872 (1990).
21
See, e.g., Lucas v. South Carolina Coastal Council, 505 U.S. 1003 (1992); see also id.at 1061 (Stevens, J., dissenting).
MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
1952
CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 21:1945principle impeaches all sense of agreement on the principle
“itself.” It would say, in effect, that disagreement over application
just is, or just does directly reflect, disagreement over what the
principle
is. And to say that would again be to flatten, this time inthe other direction, the Rosenfeldian division of polities between
homogeneous and heterogeneous.
Before examining how that bears on Rosenfeld’s project of
prescribing for a crisis, we should have a glance at his use of a
substance-procedure distinction to subdivide heterogeneous
polities into modern and postmodern types. Marking the
difference between these two kinds of polities, Rosenfeld says, is
that only in the former do we find the makings of a procedural-
although not a substantive-consensus. Here, to remind you, is his
precise statement about what it is that modern polities have and
postmodern polities lack: “a broadly based shared understanding”
about how to “handle,” by the “institutional means” of a “division
of labor between law, ethics, and politics,” the very fact of ethical
pluralism that characterizes all heterogeneous polities-that is,
their lack of agreement on “legitimate normative criteria for
evaluating laws and adjudications.”22 If that formulation does not
point to a distinction between substantive and procedural
agreement, then I do not understand what difference Rosenfeld
means to posit between the modern and postmodern subclasses of
heterogeneous polities. If, on the other hand, it does point to a
distinction between substantive and procedural agreement, then
insofar as such a distinction cannot hold up, neither, it seems, can
Rosenfeld’s distinction between modern and postmodern polities.
And in fact it is far from clear that we can finally make sense of the
idea of agreement on a procedural level, in conditions of ethical
and ideological division so deep and wide as to place beyond reach
all hope of agreement on a substantive level.23
In sum, we must doubt the ultimate maintainability, in the
relevant context, of both the insulation of principles from their
applications and the idea of a procedural-not-substantive
consensus. If our doubts are well founded, they plainly threaten
the sturdiness of both of Rosenfeld’s ideal-typical divisions of
polities-between homogeneous and heterogeneous, and, within
the heterogeneous type, between modern and postmodern. That is
22 ROSENFELD,
supra note 1, at 2, 3, 7.23
See MICHELMAN, supra note 5, at 38-39, 42-50; Michelman, supra note 3, at 1024-28.Doubts about flights from substance are a staple of recent American constitutional theory.
See, e.g.
, Richard A. Epstein, Modern Republicanism-Or the Flight from Substance, 97YALE L.J. 1633 (1988); Laurence H. Tribe,
The Puzzling Persistence of Process-BasedConstitutional Theories
, 89 YALE L.J. 1063 (1980).MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
2000]
POSTMODERN JUST INTERPETATIONS 1953important, because it prompts us to consider that perhaps the
vexations of just legal interpretation are not a crisis at all, but a
nuisance ailment of the constitutional or law-governed state. They
would be, then, like mice in the attic, not a new disease of our latearriving
postmodern polities but a chronic affliction at least as old
as the house of constitutional government.
Suppose that constitutional-democratic societies, for quite
some time now, have been so ethically or ideologically diverse that
major disagreements over the application of nominal substantive
norms have been a part of their daily, common experience. If the
insulation of a norm’s identity from its major applications does not
hold up, if obdurate disagreements over major applications are
tantamount to lack of accord on the guiding substantive principles
of interpretation “themselves,” then those same societies are, and
long have been, heterogeneous ones in Rosenfeld’s taxonomy.
Now suppose that a great many societies are, and long have been,
so ethically or ideologically divided that choices among political
institutions and processes inevitably appear to be, or to implicate,
choices among competing ideological concerns or conceptions of
the good. In other words, the distinction between procedure and
substance does not hold up in these societies. Perhaps variations
in the strictness of observance, or intensity of application, of
ostensibly procedural principles, such as separation of powers and
federalism (“states rights”), are widely perceived as ethically or
ideologically biased. Any polity of which that has been true since
some moment in the past has, over that same span of time, been
“postmodern” in Rosenfeld’s classification, a social scene in which
even the procedural constitutional essentials are sucked into the
swirl of ethical and ideological controversy. But this means that
the so-called crisis is widespread and long-standing in the world.
In other words, the implication is that what we’re looking at here is
simply a part of a normal condition in the politics of constitutional
democracy, a condition that history and experience tell us is
manageable without tears. (Got mice? Get a cat and learn to like
it.) If we now think about the types of contemporary responses to
the so-called crisis that Rosenfeld surveys in
Just Interpretations,this “false-alarm” way of viewing the matter would point strongly
toward favoring the deflationary, pragmatist approaches to the
interpretation question, such as those advanced by Richards
Posner and Rorty.24
24 ROSENFELD,
supra note 1, ch. 6. Actually, the cat in this case might look more likeRichard Fallon’s account of the conventions of American constitutional-legal argument.
Richard H. Fallon, Jr.,
A Constructivist Coherence Theory of Constitutional Interpretation,100 HARV. L. REV. 1189 (1987).
MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
1954
CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 21:1945But let us not overstate our case. To say that the
principle/application and substance/procedure distinctions do not
hold up
in the last analysis is not to say that they cannot be used todescribe significant relative differences respecting societal
consciousness
-differences large enough to imply that the problemof “just interpretation” has indeed, as Rosenfeld in effect says in
his book’s opening sentence, recently graduated from chronicnuisance
status to critical significance in the actual experience of
social life. “Interest in a subject increases dramatically,” he writes,
“when that subject becomes problematic.”25
Becomes
visibly, experientially problematic. That surely iswhat Rosenfeld means. He does not, after all, himself believe in
the analytical robustness of the distinctions out of which he builds
his table of polities. Regarding the principle/application
distinction, Rosenfeld remarks that “[i]t is only when . . . grasped
from the perspective of the conception of the good to which it
happens to be linked that the full import of [a] . . . norm can be
properly evaluated.”26 Thus, contemplating the social fact of
disagreement over the justice of killing physicians who perform
abortions, Rosenfeld finds it “unclear” whether what we witness is
consensus on a norm prohibiting “murder in general,”
accompanied by a subordinate disagreement over what constitutes
murder in certain particular contexts, or, rather, “an actual
relativism derived from an insoluble conflict among irreconcilable
conflicting conceptions of the good.”27 Rosenfeld knows that it is
not only endless variations in the adjudicative facts that stand
between a principle and its applications. Also in that space are
more general, experience-based clashes of perceptions and
understandings-“perspectives”-regarding the background
conditions, relations, needs, and interests of various groups in
society, and a nominal principle of justice driven by one of these
clashing perspectives to require race-conscious government action
(using another example) is not comfortably identical with “the
same” principle driven by another perspective to prohibit it.
The idea of procedure transcending substance fares no better
with Rosenfeld. His critical treatment of Jürgen Habermas’s selfstyled
“proceduralist” approach is precisely aimed at dispatching
that idea. By way of illustration, Rosenfeld introduces a radical
feminist challenge against the Habermasian, proceduralist
25 ROSENFELD,
supra note 1, at 1.26
Id. at 205.27 Michel Rosenfeld,
Can Human Rights Bridge the Gap Between Universalism andCultural Relativism? A Pluralist Assessment Based on the Rights of Minorities
, 30 COLUM.HUM. RTS. L. REV. 249, 253 (1999).
MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
2000]
POSTMODERN JUST INTERPETATIONS 1955paradigm of law-a challenge that shows, he says, that the
proceduralist paradigm is “buttressed by a particular conception of
law and rights.”28 “[A]ny alternative paradigm of law designed to
be consistent with the radical feminist challenge,” he says, could
not be merely a procedural one.29 “It would have to press
substantive feminist norms against masculinist objections,” and
thus would necessarily rely on “predialogical or extradialogical
sources of legitimacy.”30 “Legal interpretation,” Rosenfeld
concludes more generally, “cannot avoid reliance on substantive
normative commitments.”31
Given Rosenfeld’s own express denials of the analytical
robustness of the distinctions by which he differentiates crisis-free
homogeneous and heterogeneous-modern polities from crisisridden
heterogeneous-postmodern ones, it seems he must be
differentiating polities not in terms of categorical differences of
how law really does or does not work in them, but rather in terms
of
relative differences among people’s perceptions regarding therule of law.32 Rosenfeld is best understood to say that, depending
on the time and the place, a
prevailing sense of agreement onprinciples transcending disagreement on applications, or a
prevailing sense
of a procedural consensus transcendingsubstantive division, may or may not be capable of sustaining the
justice of legal interpretations. But would it really be
justice, then,of which we speak, or would it be the sense or perception of
justice? Are they the same thing? Can the meaning and
possibility of justice really vary in this way from time to time and
from place to place, depending on how keenly and irrepressibly
aware people are of their ethical and ideological divisions and
corresponding normative disagreements? Indeed, it would appear
so, if justice and the perception of justice are internally connected
in the way that, now for the second time, we see implied by
28 ROSENFELD,
supra note 1, at 143.29
Id.30
Id. at 143-44.31
Id. at 200. Rosenfeld allows that a prevailing procedural conception of justice canvery well transcend a specific set of substantive-normative divisions, while denying that
any procedural conception can ever transcend
all substantive issues. Id. at 137-38. Thesame point is indeed implicit in something I’ve already quoted from Rosenfeld’s text-that
is, his remark that, in postmodern polities, two developments occur in conjunction with
each other: “commonly held norms and values recede nearly completely” while, surely not
unrelatedly, “all institutional means for regulating intersubjective interaction” come to
“seem inevitably biased in favor of” one or another of the competing conceptions of the
good.
Id. at 7; see also supra text accompanying note 15.32 ROSENFELD,
supra note 1, at 5-6 (describing the transition from the modern to thepostmodern polity as one of possibly gradual “erosion” of the “persuasive” power of what
had been, after all (in modernism), a strictly “contingent” overlap between the
interpretive implications of the impulses of “naturalism” and “positivism”).
MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
1956
CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 21:1945Rosenfeld’s exposition of the crisis.
II. WHAT JUSTICE?
A.
Justice and Law: Reconciliation and Decision1. Reconciliation
In the terms favored by Rosenfeld, justice as it pertains to the
law of a pluralist society-one populated by a multiplicity of
individual and collective “selves” committed to various and
conflicting conceptions of the good and of common interest-is
part of the pursuit of a more “ultimate” good, consisting in “the
reconciliation of self and other in the least coercive and least
confining manner possible.”33 Law is the “external,” which is to
say the imposed, regulation of transactions and relations among
persons and groups. We may think of law at its best, democratic
law, as a projection outward,
from each of many individual andcollective selves
to other selves around them, of a set of bindingterms for social coexistence and cooperation. Law thus involves
an “externalization” of the self toward the others. But “external”
is a two-way street. What is outgoing must also be incoming. In
an ethically and ideologically plural society, to think of democratic
law as outgoing from the self is also, unavoidably, to think of it as
incoming upon the self.34 (“We are all selves,” it might be said by
some president from the inaugural bandstand, “we are all others.”)
Binding terms that go out from any (or all) must also come to all,
and pluralist-democratic law, then, must also and always be an
irruption or intrusion by otherness upon the self.35 Thus, at risk in
the search for just legal interpretations is intrapersonal, as well as
social, unity-the threat to the unity of the self arising not only
from the fact that any self may at any time have potentially
conflicting ethical and ideological loyalties,36 but from the two-way
structure of the externalized character of law. “When the self
presses its claims in the name of justice,” Rosenfeld observes, it
does “violence” to other and different selves. Conversely, “when
the self restrains the pursuit of its own claims to do justice to the
33
Id. at 213; see also id. at 55 (equating justice in legal meanings with “meanings thatmake for a fair equilibrium between the respective needs, interests, and aspirations of the
self and those of the other”);
id. at 225 (placing justice “among” the higher-order normsentailed by a commitment to the all-out pursuit of self-other reconciliation).
34
See id. at 236 (“[I]n any pluralist setting, any law reducible to a mere projection ofthe self (which from the vantage point of the other amounts to a mere extension of the
other) is but an illusion or an instrument of tyranny.”).
35
See id. at 60, 229-30, 235.36
See id. at 202-03.MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
2000]
POSTMODERN JUST INTERPETATIONS 1957other, it does violence to itself.”37 In the domain of pluralistdemocratic
law-Rousseau would be the inspiration here38-
justice is the reach to make political authority and its exercise as
fully as possible internal to every individual and collective self in
the neighborhood. Or, to turn the point around, justice is the
reach to make political authority as little as possible an imposition
upon any self of what that self cannot recognize as according a full
measure of respect and sympathy to its own concerns, beliefs, and
commitments-indeed, so full a measure as almost-if-not-quite to
become or identify with those concerns. In sum, a just legal order
must be one that, in its content and by its practice, caters to
self/other empathy and reconciliation.
2. Decision
But how, then, is law to be made, or experienced as,
sufficiently “severable” from ethics to allow for reconciliation
through law without suppression of “ongoing” ethical conflict-
without, that is, suppression of at least some conceptions of the
good?39 Perhaps an answer lies in the very externality and
impersonality of legal norms of conduct, their appearance to daily
experience as force-backed impositions on members of society,
generally and indifferently. Perhaps that fact about the
experiential side of legal requirements is the very thing about them
that, in many cases (certainly not all) could allow for compliance
without self-loss or self-division, insofar as it allows for the
externalization of compliance from the innermost redoubts of the
self.40
That possibility would seem to be crucial to the hope that self
and other, freedom and political authority, might be reconciled in
and through the medium of law. For to imagine that is to imagine
that controversies so hot as to endanger the unity of both society
37
Id. at 60. One can embrace the insight, as I do, while finding regrettable the nowcommonuse of “violence” in contexts such as this. If this is violence, what word have we
left for
violence?38
See id. at 219-20.39
See id. at 73-74.40
See id. at 239-40. As Rosenfeld explains:[W]ithin the perspective of comprehensive pluralism, coercion is not only
constraining, but also liberating: it allows the self to . . . [become enlisted in the
pursuit of other’s objectives] without either of them being swept into the
perspective of the other . . . [and] without [the self’s] having to express allegiance
to the [other’s] good.
Id.
This clear perception of the external force of law as a positive, integral aspect of itsdistinct value to members of society is one that Rosenfeld shares with Habermas.
Id.; seealso
Jürgen Habermas, Postscript to Faktizit?t und Geltung, 20 PHIL. & SOC. CRITICISM135, 136 (1994).
MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
1958
CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 21:1945and the self, if left for communal-ethical or majoritarian-political
resolution, can be cooled and defused by being sent instead to
resolution according to law.41 And to imagine
that is to envisionpolitical, including judicial, authority being bound by a
discretelaw, a law that is clearly detached from ethics and ideology, so that
it can-as far as it goes-displace ethical and ideological
partisanship from legislative and judicial rule. Yet this discrete
law, this law that binds authority to nonpartisanship, in order to be
just, must be a law that acts with intense respect and regard for
each of the multiple, concrete selves it touches. Just law must be
reconciliatory even as it is decisive over ethical and ideological
controversy, decisive even as it is reconciliatory, and the two
demands do not sit easily together. Demanded is a law that, while
welcoming to all ethical and ideological views and hostile to none,
is nevertheless capable, more or less objectively, of pointing to
solutions to hot controversies fueled by ethical and ideological
differences. It seems inevitable-at least to Rosenfeld and to
me-that such a
corpus juris would have to be one that casts many,if not most, of its norms in the form of what writers on
jurisprudence currently call “standards” as opposed to “rules.”42
The crisis of legal interpretation, as Rosenfeld constructs it in
JustInterpretations
, is a matter, in part, of the difficulty, under recentlyaccentuated social conditions of ethical and ideological pluralism,
of conceiving of a largely standard-based legal practice that can
satisfy both requirements together, avoiding divisive partiality
without falling into watery and useless indeterminacy, avoiding
indeterminacy without falling into partiality.
B.
The Contemporary Quest for Thinness in Principles of Justice:Political Liberalism
We seek guides to justice in the legal interpretations of a
postmodern polity. Required, it appears, are criteria neither too
thick nor too slack. Too thick a criterion will be divisive, a wedge
where we need a bond, while too slack a one will fail to provide
the special kind of external-arbitral antidote to social and personal
disintegration we can sometimes get (if Rosenfeld is right) from
routing hot controversies to legal instead of communal-ethical or
majoritarian-political resolution. Inherited criteria that appear too
41
See ROSENFELD, supra note 1, at 226, 229.42
Id. at 242-50 (calling on the method of “reversible reciprocity” to carry the lion’sshare of the legal-interpretive burden);
see also Frank I. Michelman, A Brief Anatomy ofAdjudicative Rule Formalism
, 66 U. CHI. L. REV. 934 (1999). See generally DuncanKennedy,
Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89 HARV. L. REV. 1685(1976). For a recent array of counterviews, see
Symposium: Formalism Revisited, 66 U.CHI. L. REV. 527 (1999).
MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
2000]
POSTMODERN JUST INTERPETATIONS 1959slack will have to be stiffened up; those that appear too thick will
have to be thinned out. Historically, a main direction of reform
has been toward thinning out, as the direction of social change has
been toward ethical and ideological diversification-as a “postmetaphysical”
age has succeeded its metaphysical predecessor43
and a “fact of reasonable pluralism” has emerged to proceduralize,
relatively speaking, our view of what political justice might
possibly be.44
Unmistakably, the search of the dominant, recent liberalminded
political philosophy spoken for by John Rawls and Jürgen
Habermas has been for the thinnest criteria that can still check the
disintegrative forces of diversity.45 Because it is the contemporary
alternative with which Rosenfeld’s own proposal bears closest
comparison, we may take as illustration John Rawls’s idea of a
culturally situated, political consensus on a small, substantive set of
“constitutional essentials.” The cultural situation envisioned by
Rawls is that of a wide, historical public culture of constitutional
democracy. By a “political” consensus on norms of justice, Rawls
means, among other things, one that is freestanding from all
“particular” conceptions of the good, where “particular” means
ethically or ideologically partisan
within the constitutionaldemocraticpublic culture.
The constitutional-democratic culture supplies a common
bond of recognition by each self of all others as equally the
possessors of moral capacities or “powers” and corresponding
interests in their exercise-capacities both for adopting, revising,
and pursuing one’s own conception of the good and for
recognizing and embracing fair terms of social cooperation among
persons thus constituted. “Reciprocity,” let us say, is recognition
by persons of each other as being “free and equal” through their
moral powers. Reciprocity, it is argued, allows for the emergence
of a very abstract and general, “thin” public conception of the
good as consisting in a person’s adequate stocks (so to speak) of
certain “primary goods”-rights, liberties, and opportunities;
income and wealth; the social bases of self-respect-that anyone
presumably would want, whatever his or her conception of the
good and related aims in life.46
Engagement in the spirit and practice of reciprocity, then, will
43 HABERMAS,
supra note 6, at 448.44 RAWLS,
supra note 4, at xvii-xxii.45 On the shared liberal-mindedness of Rawls and Habermas, see their well-known
exchange, Jürgen Habermas,
Reconciliation through the Public Use of Reason: Remarks onJohn Rawls’s Political Liberalism
, 92 J. PHIL. 109 (1995), and John Rawls, Reply toHabermas
, 92 J. PHIL. 132 (1995).46
See, e.g., RAWLS, supra note 4, at 75-76, 178-80; Michelman, supra note 7.MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
1960
CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 21:1945further allow-according to Rawls’s argument-for arrival at a
broadly inclusive, “overlapping” consensus, among all who are
moved by reciprocity, regarding a set of basic terms of social
cooperation bearing on the distribution of these goods, or what
Rawls calls “principles of justice” for the basic structure of society.
Importantly, Rawls means a
moral consensus, one that reflects, onthe part of all participants, a moral judgment (about what is owed
to each other by persons reciprocally recognized as free and
equal), not just a strategic one (about what will secure the better
outcomes or more favorable conditions for the self’s pursuit of its
own conception of the good). Only such a consensus can allow for
the synchronous exercise by all participants of
both the moralpowers that define them as free and equal claimants to justice-
their powers of recognition of, and compliance with, fair terms of
social cooperation as well as their powers of adoption and pursuit
of a vision of the good.47 What is “overlapping” about such a
moral consensus, among otherwise conflicting conceptions of the
good, is its dependency on-its presupposition of-the occupation
by reciprocity of a place in all the participating visions of the good.
Conceptions that have no place for reciprocity are simply excluded
as “unreasonable.”48 Justice, in Rawls’s view, is the set of
principles to govern decisions about the basic structure of society
that is emergent from an overlapping moral consensus among
conceptions of the good that include a place for reciprocity.
C.
Enter Comprehensive PluralismRosenfeld believes the crisis calls for drawing the criteria for
just legal interpretations from a normative doctrine, called
“comprehensive pluralism,” which he presents in sharp contrast to
Rawlsian political liberalism. I do not here undertake to give this
proposal the full introduction it deserves, or even to begin to
indicate the refinement, care, and subtlety of Rosenfeld’s full
exposition of it.49 I treat it strictly and crudely with a view to a
particular reservation I want to raise about the proposal, based (no
doubt unfairly) on my particular curiosity about how Rosenfeld
precisely means to differentiate it-as he outspokenly does-from
the “political” liberalism of John Rawls.50
Comprehensive pluralism, to begin with, is a frankly
substantive, frankly ethical, frankly contentious doctrine, one that
47
See Frank I. Michelman, The Subject of Liberalism, 46 STAN. L. REV. 1807, 1829(1994).
48
See RAWLS, supra note 4, at 60-61.49 Your only valid recourse is to see chapters 7 and 8 of ROSENFELD,
supra note 1.50
See infra text accompanying notes 7-8.MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
2000]
POSTMODERN JUST INTERPETATIONS 1961posits a distinct, substantive theory of value or of the good, of what
is worth pursuing in human life. It conceives of the good as
success in the promotion of “peaceful coexistence among[] as
many competing theories of the good as possible.”51 We are not to
understand this as expressing a quasi-aesthetic sensibility that finds
beauty, stimulation, or richness of life in the vision of a thousand
flowers blooming. Rosenfeld is no liberal “perfectionist,”52 and his
comprehensive-pluralist conception of the good is not in that way
a freestanding one. It is rather parasitic on the “pluralism in fact”
that characterizes postmodern polities. The value-the good-
conceived by comprehensive pluralism lies exactly in solicitude for
the multitude of individual and collective selves that in fact there
are, and are bound to be, in all such polities. It lies in the very
avoidance, insofar as possible, of divisive and oppressive intrusion
upon those selves. The point about “pluralism as norm,” as
Rosenfeld succinctly put it, is that it is “best for pluralism in fact.”53
Comprehensive pluralism is all the same a “non-neutral”
conception of the good. It competes directly with all of the other
ethical conceptions that jostle for space and privilege in
postmodern polities. Seemingly paradoxically, Rosenfeld posits a
particular, partisan, fighting faith, the observance of which may
nevertheless bring a valuable kind of unity to a society inhabited
by many other partisan fighting faiths. Obviously, such a result is
not possible unless there is something to differentiate the ethic of
comprehensive pluralism categorically from all the other ethics
and ideologies whose reconciliation comprehensive pluralism
supposedly is going to effectuate. There must be some way in
which comprehensive pluralism occupies a different conceptual
plane from that of the other competitors. At the same time, the
differentiating notion must be one that does not disguise the
character of comprehensive pluralism as itself a nonnecessitated,
partisan and particular matter of ethical substance.54 It is to meet
this need that Rosenfeld has introduced the idea of a class of
“second-order” ethical conceptions, the members of which (but, of
course, there is only one of these, comprehensive pluralism) stand
in a different relation to all of the first-order ethical conceptions
than does any one of them to the rest (but, of course, the special
relationship can’t be that of neutrality between itself and any of
51 ROSENFELD,
supra note 1, at 200.52 Compare JOSEPH RAZ, THE MORALITY OF FREEDOM (1996).
53 ROSENFELD,
supra note 1, at 207; see also id. (“Comprehensive pluralism . . . yieldsthe best possible normative criterion for the reconciliation of self and other within a
pluralistic in fact society, in a way that maximizes the potential for justice while
minimizing that for violence.”).
54 As for why this “must” be so, see
infra text accompanying notes 60-61.MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
1962
CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 21:1945them). But then what can this second-orderness possibly be?
How can comprehensive pluralism’s demand for placing all
conceptions of the good on an equal footing prevail over rival
ethical claims, given that its call is, after all, to place all
conceptions of the good on an equal footing?55
Is that, after all, such a hard question? There you are,
committed to a normative doctrine of maximum equal solicitude
for all conceptions of the good. You want to set that doctrine to
ruling over all conceptions of the good, in the sense of mediating
and arbitrating conflicts among them in accord with its precept of
maximum equal solicitude. It seems you can easily do so without
any hint of paradox or contradiction. You simply refuse to classify
your super-doctrine as a doctrine of the good. You classify it,
instead, as a doctrine of the right. That is how John Rawls does it,
to take a notable example.
Rawls, but not Rosenfeld. Rosenfeld decidedly refuses this
easy answer to what must then remain, indeed, a very hard and
puzzling question. Why does he? And what are the
consequences?
D.
Rosenfeld Contra Rawls1. A Similarity of Opposites?
On the surface, at least, Rosenfeldian comprehensive
pluralism bears many striking resemblances to Rawlsian political
liberalism. At the core of both doctrines is the teaching that
justice in law and politics depends on our finding a higher-order
normative conception that, while frankly substantive, is also
sufficiently thin to accommodate a broad range of extant ethical
views. Rosenfeldian second-orderness is, in this respect, a gesture
to thinness, structurally comparable to Rawlsian overlapping
consensus.
Both theories also include a resigned acceptance, even so, of a
filter for “unreasonable” ethical views (as Rawls calls them), views
insufficiently committed to what both authors call “reciprocity,”
meaning acceptance of the full equality of the claim of every
individual (and, for Rosenfeld, collective) self to respect and
accommodation from others.56 Both theories use a notion of
55
See ROSENFELD, supra note 1, at 206-07.56
See supra text accompanying notes 45-48; see also ROSENFELD, supra note 1, at 209(“[A] crusading religion, for which conversion of the infidel, by force if necessary, is a
sacred duty that admits of no exceptions, has no place in comprehensive pluralism.”);
id. at213-14 (calling reciprocity a central value in comprehensive pluralism).
MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
2000]
POSTMODERN JUST INTERPETATIONS 1963primary goods.57
But of course it is those things that are structurally most
similar that also stand to be most sharply opposed in meaning-
and opposition, not identity, of meaning is how Rosenfeld
understands the relation between the comprehensive pluralism he
sponsors and Rawlsian political liberalism. The whole story lies
compacted in the key passage I quoted near the outset:
[T]o the extent that comprehensive pluralism amounts to yet
another conception of the good, it is clearly distinguishable
from contemporary Kantian visions such as those Habermas or
of Rawls in
A Theory of Justice. On the other hand, to theextent that comprehensive pluralism is more than yet another
conception of the good, in that it unleashes an inevitable but
ultimately resolvable dialectic between first-order and secondorder
norms, it differs markedly from theories based on
building an “overlapping consensus,” such as that elaborated by
Rawls in
Political Liberalism, and from all theories ultimatelyreducible to mere relativism.58
2. The Right and the Good
We need some conceptual tools for unpacking this dense
passage. One that will come in handy is the Rawlsian notion of
“the priority of the right over the good.”59
The question of “the right” asks what ought to be done, all
morally relevant factors considered, while the question of “the
good” asks what is of value to a person, group, or society, or what
contributes value to a person’s life, a group’s existence, or a
society’s history. In the field of social policy, at least, these two
questions have appeared to many not to be identical. A chief
reason is that, even if we had universal agreement on, say, glory as
the ultimate good for humankind, we would still have to face a
distributional question: Are we to aim for the glory of society as a
whole, or for that of the individuals and groups composing it? If of
individuals, is our aim to be the greatest achievable aggregate sum
of individual glory scores? The greatest average glory of
individuals? Equality of glory among individuals? The greatest
glory of the least glorious person? Or what? Resolution of these
questions of aggregation and distribution seems necessarily to
depend on considerations that cannot already be contained in the
idea of the ultimate goodness of human glory, and those
considerations, then, are considerations of the right as
57
See supra text accompanying note 46; see also ROSENFELD, supra note 1, at 262-63.58 ROSENFELD,
supra note 1, at 201.59
See, e.g., JOHN RAWLS, A THEORY OF JUSTICE 31 (1971).MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
1964
CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 21:1945distinguished from the good.
Speaking more intuitively, the notion of the priority of the
right over the good is that there are certain constraints on action,
including political action, that persons owe to each other out of
reciprocal regard for one another as free and equal individuals,60
regardless of what idea of the good anyone (or everyone) may
happen to hold. Compliance with the demands of the right is thus
conceived as preconditional to anyone’s and everyone’s normative
permission to pursue the good, in something like the way in which
compliance with the legal norms in a constitutional bill of rights is
preconditional to legal permission to pursue public policy
objectives through lawmaking. The term “deontological” is often
used to designate the class of normative theories that posit such a
relationship of right-before-good preconditionality.
3. Deontology and Oppression
With this notion in hand, we return to our key passage. Let us
focus for a bit on the first sentence. It says, in effect, that
Rosenfeld is not a deontological theorist-that Rosenfeldian
comprehensive pluralism is not to be regarded as a doctrine of the
right, as such to be differentiated from, or prioritized over, any and
all doctrines of the good. True (anticipating the second sentence
in our key passage), the pursuit of comprehensive pluralism has
“second-order” status as compared with the first-order status of all
other ethical commitments, but the first sentence, by its
repudiation of “Kantian” views, tells us that the second-order/firstorder
relation is
not the relation of preconditionality thatdeontological theories posit between compliance with the right
and the pursuit of the good. It cannot be, if comprehensive
pluralism is what Rosenfeld tells us it is-a conception of the good,
competing, as such, with other conceptions of the good.
Of course, this first sentence does not stand alone, and its full
meaning cannot be extracted without consideration of its
qualifying successor. It is nevertheless worth pausing briefly,
before moving on, to ask what might motivate this rather preciouslooking
insistence on Rosenfeld’s part on distancing his theory
from the deontological (“Kantian”) tradition. A likely answer lies
in a concern about oppression. When we do come to the next
sentence, we shall find embedded in it a cautiousness about the
way in which ostensible doctrines of impartiality among
perspectives may end up giving some perspectives the upper hand
over others. Worries of that sort light easily upon normative
60
See supra text accompanying note 47.MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
2000]
POSTMODERN JUST INTERPETATIONS 1965doctrines that appear to privilege themselves, as doctrines of right,
over others that are plainly and frankly mere doctrines of the
good. It is therefore no surprise to find Rosenfeld rejecting any
such claim of privilege for comprehensive pluralism.
And yet, as a criterion for just legal interpretations, defined as
interpretations that “make for a fair equilibrium between the
respective needs, interests, and aspirations of the self and those of
the other,”61 comprehensive pluralism obviously cannot be just
another conception of the good amid all the rest. It must also be
something special, second-order, reminiscent of a Rawlsian
overlapping consensus. And so it is. But the burden of the second
sentence of our key quotation is that the structural similarity to
Rawls is decidedly of the oppositional kind.
In that sentence, Rosenfeld points to the “dialectic” that
comprehensive pluralism sets going between itself and all of the
first-order ethical conceptions as the factor that differentiates
comprehensive pluralism from all competing theories of justice for
postmodern polities. On that basis, he sets comprehensive
pluralism in opposition to “theories reducible to mere relativism.”
That
claim is easy enough to grasp. Here, “dialectic” signifiesconflict or contention; a “dialectical” relation between norms is
always and interminably a contentious one. True, the term may
also signify a perception that the conflict occurs within a higherlevel
harmony, but we don’t need that wrinkle to see how an
ethical norm that can enter into contentious relations with others
stands opposed to relativism. “Relativism,” after all, is defined by
Rosenfeld precisely as the view that rules out the very idea of
anysemantic contact, contentious or non-contentious, between any
pair of ethical norms. It is the view that “all value preferences are
ultimately purely subjective and so contextually bound to the
conception of the good from which they emerge that it would be
meaningless to seek to gauge them from the standpoint of any
other perspective.”62 Comprehensive pluralism is obviously antirelativist,
then, in the sense that it is itself a committed ethical
stance from which to “gauge” and deal with conflicts among other
ethical views and between any of them and itself.
61 ROSENFELD,
supra note 1, at 55; see also supra note 33 and accompanying text.62 ROSENFELD,
supra note 1, at 206. Again we recall the insight offered by Rosenfeldpondering the debate over the moral permissibility of abortions, or of their prevention by
the killing of those who perform them, where the question is cast as that of whether either
class of acts is correctly subsumed under a commonly accepted norm prohibiting murder.
The case, he suggested, may be better described as one of “an actual relativism derived
from an insoluble conflict among irreconcilably conflicting conceptions of the good” than
as one of agreement on a norm accompanied by disagreement over its application.
Seesupra
text accompanying note 27.MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
1966
CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 21:1945Rosenfeld speaks not just of differentiating comprehensive
pluralism from relativist theories, but, more complicatedly, of
differentiating it from “theories based on building an ‘overlapping
consensus,’ such as that elaborated by Rawls in
PoliticalLiberalism
, and from all theories ultimately reducible to mererelativism.” That construction
could be read as implying politicalliberalism’s membership in the family of theories that are
“ultimately reducible” to relativism. But we ought not thus to
read it. Critiques of political-not-comprehensive liberalism occur
elsewhere in Rosenfeld’s text, and they show clearly that
Rosenfeld cannot intend an accusation of relativism against the
Rawlsian doctrine.
It is precisely in relation to the idea of a political-notcomprehensive
normative (“overlapping”) consensus that
Rosenfeld expressly develops his concerns about the oppressive
potential of normative doctrines that present themselves as
different in kind, or quality, from frankly partisan conceptions of
the good. Rosenfeld rejects, as incapable of sympathetic response
to the full range of ethical and ideological commitments that
postmodern polities have to accommodate, a conception of justice
as “mere” reciprocity. Such a conception works by “reducing” self
and other to the sameness of being each a “possessor of a
perspective,” while glossing over the concrete realities of those
perspectives. It excessively “stresses identities at the expense of
differences.”63 It will fail to achieve justice because it “lacks the
means to constrain a dominant self to acknowledge the needs and
aspirations rooted in the perspective of the other as opposed to
those traceable to the other possessing a perspective.”64 In other
words, the strategy of prescinding from concrete conflict to a
search for more abstract principles that all can accept in the spirit
of reciprocity is objectionable for its indulgence of the self in
refusal to confront and come to terms with otherness in all its
living specificity and concreteness.65 Such a strategy, Rosenfeld
believes, is bound to end, when push comes to shove, in concrete
cases, by giving some perspectives the upper hand over others
under an inevitably false guise of neutrality among perspectives.66
(The question of holding principles separate from their
applications is now upon us with a vengeance.) In sum, Rosenfeld
finds potentially oppressive Rawls’s claim that a quasi-universally
63 ROSENFELD,
supra note 1, at 244-45.64
Id. at 245.65
See SEYLA BENHABIB, The Generalized and the Concrete Other, in SITUATING THESELF 148, 158-59 (1992).
66 ROSENFELD,
supra note 1, at 127-28.MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
2000]
POSTMODERN JUST INTERPETATIONS 1967cognizable constitutional-democratic culture-the common
culture, as Rawls conceives it, of law-governed, free societies-can
support a substantive conception of justice that is nevertheless
strictly “political,” not itself reflecting any conception of the good
so distinctive or “particular” that members of society will
experience it as a partisan, fighting faith among other partisan,
fighting faiths. Rosenfeld cannot, therefore, be thinking of the
political-liberal stance as one that is tantamount to relativism, the
meta-ethical doctrine most apparently designed to be guaranteed
free of all such oppressive potential.
To the contrary, anti-relativism is a shared feature of the
justice theories of Rosenfeld and Rawls, one to be added to the list
of similarities we have already compiled.67 Both doctrines
refusethe relativist route to avoidance of potential for oppressiveness.
And the question still hangs, then, about what the crucial
difference, in this respect, is supposed to be between them.
Exactly how is it that committed, anti-relativist, comprehensive
pluralism avoids the potential for oppressiveness that committed,
anti-relativist, political liberalism involves? Taking Rosenfeld at
his word, the answer lies in the “inevitable but ultimately
resolvable dialectic between [itself] and [other] ethical
conceptions” that comprehensive pluralism sets up but that a
consensus-based, deontological doctrine like political liberalism
does not.
Of course, that response, while asserting a crucial difference
between the two normative doctrines before us, also again reminds
us of the structural similarity between them. Both are two-level
constructions. Both locate the possibility of justice and legitimacy
in politics in the relationship they contemplate between the norms
that respectively occupy their higher and lower levels. For
Rosenfeld, that means the openly contentious relationship
between the uniquely second-order ethical conception of
comprehensive pluralism and its first order competitors. For
Rawls, it means the ideally inclusionary relationship between the
“political” consensus on principles of justice and the
comprehensive ethical views participating in the consensus.
We have seen that it is this very holding-out of the possibility
of a public conception of the right in politics, to which all
“reasonable” comprehensive views can willingly and
wholeheartedly subscribe, that Rosenfeld finds dangerous in
Rawlsian theory. And yet the puzzle remains, for Rosenfeld, too,
needs a second-order normative conception that will, at the
67
See supra text accompanying notes 56-57.MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
1968
CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 21:1945moment of application to contested cases, achieve “reconciliation”
among the contesting first-order ethics and ideologies. He needs,
as his words indicate, a second-order conception whose
contentious relation to any of the first-order ones is ultimately as
“resolvable” as it is “inevitable.” If Rosenfeld is not speaking in
riddles, only one possibility remains: In Rosenfeld’s parlance,
“reconciliation” (or “resolution”) between comprehensive
pluralism and the first-order ethical conceptions over whose
conflicts it mediates does not consist in any sort of agreement on
the latter’s part to the former’s claim to be correct as a theory of
the good.
But how, then, are we to make sense of this notion of ethical
reconciliation without ethical agreement, as a matter of the actual
experiences of selves in society? On an experiential level, how can
any self-respecting self, confronting others whose projects conflict
with its own, allow itself to be “reconciled” to legislatively and
adjudicatively imposed arbitrations, when those arbitrations
avowedly have been cast to meet the requirements of a conception
of the good with which that self decidedly does not agree? What
do we imagine going on with that self at the moment of
reconciliation?
Something, it would seem, like this.
In its experience ofreconciliation, the self, involved in some first-order conception of
the good, both perceives itself to be getting a fair shake from
comprehensive pluralism and perceives comprehensive pluralism to
be a normative doctrine to which it stands opposed, taking that
doctrine as one concerned with the question of the good.
This is farfrom impossible to understand. What is fair among persons
committed to sundry conceptions of the good is one sort of
question. What the good is for me, for you, or for humankind is
quite obviously an entirely different sort of question. One need
not in the least accept the claims of comprehensive pluralism to
state a correct theory of the good, in order believe that
comprehensive pluralism delivers fair results when elaborated into
a set of guides for the arbitration of disputes among conflicting
selves, defined in terms of the conflicting conceptions of the good
to which they hold.
I put the matter as I have in hopes of showing how the
dialectical kinship of Rosenfeld and Rawls persists, even to this
penultimate point in our analysis. Rawls, after all, would be the
last to deny the possibility of every (reasonable) self’s finding, in a
normative doctrine that many of these selves do not accept as a
doctrine
of the good, an apt design for giving every self a fair shakein the arbitration of conflicts among their diverse ethical
MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
2000]
POSTMODERN JUST INTERPETATIONS 1969commitments. Nothing, Rawls might well say, could more
exquisitely express the notion of a doctrine
of the right (not thegood) and the “priority” of the former over the latter. What
Rosenfeld has done, Rawls might well say, for all intents and
purposes, is to make comprehensive pluralism figure for the self in
question as a doctrine of the right, privileged in the way that any
such doctrine always is with respect to doctrines of the good.
Can a reconciliation of Rosenfeld and Rawls really be had on
those terms? Does not the first sentence of our key quotation
exclude it, by rejecting, on anti-oppression grounds we have
reviewed, all reliance on the Kantian idea of the priority of the
right over the good? Maybe so, maybe not. If the only exegetical
test here is one of analytical coherence and consistency, then
perhaps the first sentence appears satisfiable by splitting the
standpoints of dispensers and receivers of justice. We could
stipulate that comprehensive pluralism, and the second-order
norms to which it gives rise, figure
for those who apply them asdoctrines of the good and only as doctrines of the good. They
could still, then, figure,
for the claimants to justice to whoseconflicts and controversies they are applied
, as doctrines of the rightand not of the good.
Interestingly, Rosenfeld’s text does ask us to hold these two
standpoints apart. “[C]omprehensive pluralism,” Rosenfeld
writes, “maintains a split between demands for justice predicated
on first-order norms and legitimate endeavors to dispense justice,
which must look, above all, to second-order norms.”68 It “requires
the legal interpreter to be guided by second-order norms while
urging those who submit claims . . . to remain as true to the firstorder
norms to which they are committed as is possible consistent
with genuine acceptance of the dictates of legitimate judicial
adjudication.”69 As far as they go, those words seem compatible
with attribution to
the recipients of justice of the experience of aRawlsian overlapping consensus, among multiple conceptions of
the good, on a single conception of the right. And as long as
thedispensers of justice
steer clear of the idea that the norms theyapply are somehow
wertfrei, above the fray, the oppressivepotential that Rosenfeld finds in the idea of the priority of the
right would seem to be at least in some measure averted.
It may be a strained reading, but consider the alternative.
Rejecting it would force us to rewrite in starker form, as follows,
our experiential rendition of the Rosenfeldian notion of
reconciliation-without-agreement:
In its experience of68 ROSENFELD,
supra note 1, at 201.69
Id.MICHELMAN-BR WEBGALLEYS1.DOC 08/07/00 1:47 PM
1970
CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 21:1945reconciliation, the self, involved in some first-order conception of
the good, both perceives itself to be getting a fair shake from
comprehensive pluralism and perceives comprehensive pluralism to
be a doctrine of the good to which it stands opposed.
Period. (Noescape by having the justice-receiving self regard comprehensive
pluralism as an above-the-fray, noncompetitive doctrine of the
right and not of the good.) And then what we would have is an
exquisite expression not of the priority of the right over the good,
but of something else, something opposite-namely, a Rawlsian
bare
modus vivendi. We would have finally before us, courtesy ofRosenfeld, the very essence of
modus vivendi-that is, acceptanceby all of a principle or principles for the guidance of legal
interpretation, on strictly strategic grounds and without any
supporting normative agreement, whether on a conception of the
good perceived to underlie the principles or on the principles
themselves as an apt expression of the right.
In postmodern conditions, it seems, we do not look for
convergence on ideas of the good. Normative convergence is
possible, if at all, only on an idea of the right standing free from
ideas of the good. The difference between Rosenfeld and Rawls, if
there is one-a question I leave open-is that, where Rawls sees a
way to reconciliation through agreement on principles understood
to be principles of right and not of good,70 Rosenfeld does not.
The idea of the right prior to the good is, for him, too fraught with
risk of subverting the achievement of a “fair equilibrium between
the respective needs, interests, and aspirations of the self and those
of the other,” or what he calls justice.71
If that is finally the way we read him, then Rosenfeld’s
message is that, in the pursuit of social unity and cohesion in
postmodern polities,
modus vivendi is all we can have. To ask formore is unduly to risk subverting the pursuit. The aim is to
redeem what we can from postmodern ethical and ideological
disagreement. Whether
justice would be found in the salvage is aquestion to ponder.
70
See supra text accompanying notes 59-60.71 ROSENFELD,
supra note 1, at 55; see also supra note 33 and accompanying text.