公 法 评 论 |
惟愿公平如大水滚滚,使公义如江河滔滔! |
GLJ Vol. 2 No. 17 - 01 November 2001 - Legal Culture
Lex Mercatoria: A Reflexive Law Guide To An Autonomous Legal System
By Dr. Gralf-Peter Calliess
[0] EDITORIAL: The following paper was presented at the Transnational Law
Conference 2001, at the Center of Transnational Law (CENTRAL) at the University
of Münster on 26 October 2001 (http://www.transnational-law.de). Under the
title "Transnational Business in the Age of Globalization", the
Conference – constituting also the day of the inaugurating launch of CENTRAL's
Transnational Law Data Base (http://www.tldb.de) - brought together Lawyers,
Judges, Arbitrators, Political Scientists as well as Sociologists, all of
whom have long been working in the field of transnational law or, to use more
frequent names, the lex mercatoria or law merchant. Building upon the practical
expertise gained by some participants having served on arbitration tribunals
or within other transnational law making agencies such as the UNCITRAL or
the UNIDROIT Institute, the conference provided a forum for first-hand information
and thought exchange. At the same time, CENTRAL's very focus on developments
in transnational law naturally reach out to a wide range of interdisciplinary
research, aptly represented by the Speakers and Discussants at the conference.
Jurisprudence meets International Relations, Legal Pluralism meets Political
Science, Comparative Law meets Anthropology, Law meets Politics. The research
agenda could not be more ambitious, as we find ourselves confronted with the
emergence of intricately complex forms of international public and private
governance, involving new actors and instruments which tend to supplement
or substitute traditional ways of conceiving of international relations, comparative
and international law. International Law's original exclusive focus on states
as legal subjects falls short of assessing the manifold picture of non-state
actors on the international stage. Against this background, International
Law, being a discipline usually administered by public lawyers, increasingly
finds itself challenged and provoked by tireless private lawyers, sociologists,
political scientists and anthropologists, offering insight into and critique
of a field, which tends to escape our used ways of separating state and market,
public and private. From this perspective, the border transgressing business
transaction related to hugely voluminuous infrastructure building creates
just as many new questions as do the media propelled indictments of human
rights violations, that become known only through highly decentralized processes
of scandalization.(N)? While Gralf Calliess' paper would thus fit into practically
any sector of the Journal, we place it in our Legal Culture sector, hoping
both to express our interest in the emerging disciplinary research agendas
which so readily spring from Gralf's analysis of the legal quality of lex
mercatoria, and also to underline the challenging cross-discipline nature
of the following.
[1] In this presentation(1) I shall start with a brief introduction into the concept of Reflexive Law (Part I), in order to examine what makes especially Reflexive Law a promising candidate for a fruitful contribution to the ongoing debate on the normative-legal or mere social-factual status of Lex Mercatoria (Part II), and finally coming up with the suggestion of some criteria or features, which we should draw special attention on in the process of the emergence of a New Law Merchant as an autonomous legal system (Part III).
I. The Concept of Reflexive Law
[2] The term "Reflexive Law" was first introduced back in 1982 by
Gunther Teubner.(2) Published shortly before Helmut Kohl became German chancellor
the article was written in a context, where the social-liberal dreams of a
political reform of society, guided by scientific-rational planning and implemented
by social-engineers through the means of law had collapsed some years ago
and the only alternative rising from the dust of general disillusionment with
a supposedly omnipotent government were the neo-liberal and neo-conservative
programmes of Thatcherism and Reagonomics. Under these circumstances Reflexive
Law was a somewhat clairvoyant anticipation of the late Nineties ideas of
Tony Blair and Gerhard Schr?der on a "third way" between market
and state; on a Civil Society basically regulating itself, supported, if necessary
activated, but essentially merely framed and supervised by the State. That
is to say regulated self-regulation is the core political concept behind Reflexive
Law. However, Reflexive Law is not meant to be a political concept in itself.
To the detriment, like self-regulation it is a concept which potentially fits
to all kinds of policies, from neo-conservative subsidiarity, over neo-liberal
spontaneous ordering in free markets, to neo-socialist or communitarian ideas
of democratic self-government in small and cosy parts of society.
[3] In terms of legal theory Reflexive Law is quite a German concept in that
it is built – again as a kind of third way - on the descriptivist Systems
Theory of Niklas Luhmann(3) and the normativist Discourse Theory of Jürgen
Habermas(4) . Although Teubner's book on "Law as Autopoietic System"(5)
of 1989, in which the concept of Reflexive Law is elaborated, seems to be
somewhat cynical and, therefore, is perceived to be a mere application of
Systems Theory, there is still a lot of normative hope that we find in it,
that is to say: self-regulation symbolizes Kant′s perception of freedom and
autonomy as self-legislation whereas regulated represents Hegel′s hope for
solidarity and rational integration of society through the State.
[4] Teubner makes a creative use of these theories by stressing the similarities
rather than the differences between them. These common grounds are: Both,
Luhmann and Habermas, reconstruct modern society as a communicative system,
thus putting the focus neither on individuals and their actions nor on social
structures and organisations, but on the process of communication. Social
structures like norms, organisations, and institutions are produced and reproduced
in these communicative processes. Since it is impossible for a social theory
to predict the actual outcome of these manifold and highly complex processes,
the emphasis is on the structures and rules which govern communication. The
object of both theories, therefore, are the Meta-Rules and Meta-Structures
constituting the communication society, be that the procedural discourse rules
of Habermas, or the structures of social systems and subsystems of Luhmann.
[5] So how come the term "Reflexive Law"? The use of reflexive as
an adjective to Law is ambiguous, thereby perfectly symbolizing the intended
undecisiveness of the concept in terms of Discourse vs. Systems Theory. The
implications are threefold:
(1) Reflexive describes "an action that is directed back upon itself".
For the purposes of Systems Theory reflexivity is defined as the application
of a process to itself, e.g. "thinking of thinking", "communicating
about communication", "teaching how to teach" etc. In the context
of law reflexivity could be "making laws on law-making", "adjudicating
on adjudication", or "regulating self-regulation". It is obvious,
that the focus of Reflexive Law in this context is rather on procedural than
on substantive law, or as H.L.A. Hart put it, on secondary rather than on
primary rules. It follows, that the term Reflexive Law on the level of norms
marks rules of competence and jurisdiction, of form and of procedure, all
of which constitute the communicative processes by which society (including
law) is regulating itself. In other words, Reflexive Law deals with Constitutions
in a broad, non-technical sense. A good comparison can be seen in the contemporary
work being done under the label of New Constitutional Economics.
(2) Another meaning of reflexive is "marked by or capable of reflection",
referring to reflexion in its philosophical meaning of "introspective
contemplation or consideration of some subject matter". Here one can
find the normative implications of Reflexive Law as being connected with a
concept of rationality. However, rationality is not understood as a quality
of norms, but in accordance with Discourse Theory rather as communicative
rationality. In a nutshell, decision-making in a reflexive legal system shall
be marked by thorough deliberation or reasoning as well as by reflection on
the specific function and limits of law in modern society. Teubner suggests,
that such reflection would lead to a non-interventionist model of the State
and of Law the latter of which is essentially limits itself to what we can
call the constitutionalisation of self-regulation.
(3) Finally, a third meaning of reflexive is "a relation that exists
between and entity and itself", i.e. a concept of self-reference. This
leads us to the very basic concept of Autopoiesis. Let me try it again in
a nutshell: Autopoieses is the self-reproduction of a system out of its own
components. If a social system by definition consists out of communications,
then Autopoiesis marks nothing else but the features of the system which provide
for enduring communication, so that the system will not come to a sudden halt.
The implications for Law as Autopoietic System are as follows: the core operations
of the legal system, defined by itself as legal acts, e.g. adjudicating, legislating,
contracting and the like, must be linked with each other in a way, that the
mere existence of one such act provokes others, making reference to the first
and thereby literally producing each other. An example for such an interlinkage
of legal acts is the reference to precedent or stare decisis, by which a judgement
selectively refers to some other judgements, thereby evoking the impression
that it is a product of the quoted judgements. Another example is the strange
interrelation between statute and judgement, where the binding act of law
making produces the court decision, which at the same time by means of interpretation
in the hermeneutic circle produces and reproduces the norm.(6)
II. Lex Mercatoria: a reflexive approach to Law and Social Norms
[6] Let me proceed with the second part, in which I intend to explain in more
detail the differences, resulting from a reflexive law approach to our reflections
on the concept of law and the qualities, distinguishing it from social norms.
[7] The traditional approach in jurisprudence refers to a legal system as
a body of norms. Consequently the first 20 years of the debate over a New
Law Merchant was dedicated to the question, which norms (if any) are part
of or form this Lex Mercatoria and where these norms stem from. On this level
of norms there are, generally speaking, two ways of giving an answer:
(1) First of all, a grip to the stars, to abstract natural law: general principles
of law, human rights, the decalog, the common core of legal systems and the
like. Obviously the Unidroit or Lando Principles belong to this category.
(2) Alternatively a step into the mud of facticity, i.e. concrete natural
law: the essence or nature of things, custom, living law, etc. Here we find
standardised contract terms, trade customs and the like.
[8] The problem with these approaches is, that they instantly provoke some
standard positivist objections regarding (a) the definition of a validity
test for such norms (i.e. Harts rule of recognition), (b) the legitimacy of
law-making, (c) the completeness of a system of norms, and (d) the enforcement
of these norms. Whereas the enforcement problem can easily be overcome within
the framework of arbitration by reference to the UNCITRAL Model Law on International
Commercial Arbitration, respective national Arbitration Laws as well as the
1958 New York Convention on the Recognition and Enforcement of Foreign Arbitral
Awards(7) , the issues of validity, legitimacy and completeness result in
a vicious circle of theoretical strange loops and tautologies. It is for this
reason that the New Law Merchant during the last decades developed mainly
in practice under the auspices of "Cartesian pragmatism", as Klaus
Peter Berger has so aptly put it.(8)
[9] Let us now turn to the possible contributions of the reflexive law approach:
First of all, Systems Theory is obviously a useful analytical tool in the
debate on transnational law, since it claims that Law and Politics in general
are two separate and independent social systems. The intertwining of law and
politics in the Constitutional Nation State in this perspective is rather
a very modern and special case in social evolution. A Global Law without a
State thus is a phenomenon, which Systems Theory is readily prepared to conceptualize.(9)
[10] However, more important are the differences which result from the shift
of the theoretical focus from the level of norms to the level of communication.
Suddenly things are very easy, for all law is positive law, i.e. is valid
only by decision. To form a legal system one basically needs three communications,
each raising a normative claim of validity (i.e. prescriptive speech acts):
(1) a claimant (ego), (2) a defendant (alter), and (3) a court (alter ego,
generalised other). These communicative acts constitute a legal system by
using the Code legal/illegal (lawful/unlawful). There is no need for norms,
at least not for a complete set of rules. Norms will just come naturally with
the decisions, i.e. as the ratio decedendi of adjudication. Norms as the structure
of a legal system are thus produced by communication, as a by-product of processing
legal acts. However, a single judgment might not be sufficient to produce
a norm, for norms are more abstract, they are a generalisation out of several
judgments, and they are more stable, than a single case decision.
[11] Here we come back to Autopoiesis, which we defined as the mutual and
perpetual referencing of different legal communications. The generation of
norms is subject to the logics of remembering and forgetting, i.e. the selectivity
of the communication process, by which some communicative offers for connection
are accepted through reference by following communications, others are falling
in oblivion. Norms thus are condensed and confirmed in the enduring process
of legal discourse. To give an example, on the one hand there are judgments
which somehow become leading cases or even passages from textbooks, quoted
over and over again, while on the other hand there might be formal positive
statutes which are not applied over a period of 25 years. Which norm is more
valid, the latter or the former? For a lawyer from a Common Law background
the answer might be not too puzzling.
[12] As a result we can say, that all it needs for Lex Mercatoria to become
a legal system is a court, that adjudicates on it, and – even more important
– loads of disputes, offered by the international commercial community for
decision under the code of Law Merchant. Lex Mercatoria as a system of norms
will then flourish quasi automatically (or autopoietically) through the means
of codensation and confirmation.
III. New Law Merchant: A Global Legal System beyond the Nation State?
[13] In conclusion, let me briefly discuss some features of the New Law Merchant,
which from a Reflexive Law perspective should be highlighted as crucial in
its development towards an autonomous legal system.
[14] Let me start with the courts, since they form the centre of a legal system.
So where precisely do we find the courts deciding on and thereby condensing
and confirming the rules of a New Law Merchant? The national court-systems
are not allowed to apply non-state-law. Only arbitral tribunals under certain
arbitration laws may do so, if the parties have chosen to subject their dispute
to general principles of law and the like. The problem is here with a lack
of continuity and publicity, which hinder or even prevent the Autopoiesis
of Lex Mercatoria. To give an example: In his contribution to last years CENTRAL-Conference
Klaus Peter Berger cited Thayer on the Ancient Law Merchant as follows:
"The voices of the consuls of the sea in Genoa an Barcelona found a ready
echo in the maritime tribunals of Bristol and Ipswich, where the court sat
on the beach and dispensed justice to passing mariners between tide and tide."(10)
[15] Here we see a court as a physically localised institution, offering its
dispute resolution services. It sits on the beach, close to demand at the
dispute-market, thus providing easy access to justice. But dispute resolution
is only a service provided, but not an end in itself. For a legal system has
the function of producing certainty in normative expectations for a community
subjected to its jurisdiction. For "Certainty is so essential, that law
cannot even be just without it", as Francis Bacon observed. Or as the
Law and Economics approach would put it, law is all about reducing transaction
costs. But as we have seen above, norms and thus certainty can only be generated,
if the legal system provides for self-reference, thus starting the process
of condensation and confirmation of norms according to the logics of remembering
and forgetting.
[16] One possible feature of a legal system, enabling Autopoiesis, is a locally
institutionalised court, which will develop a kind of collective or institutional
memory. Under the very basic rule of formal justice, i.e. treating equal cases
equal, the court on the beach will start its own legal history and decide
repeating disputes by reference to its own precedent. Another very important
feature is, that the court sits in public, thereby allowing its rulings to
be spread through oral tradition by the observing mariners and finally to
be echoed by other tribunals and vice versa. As a result, over time there
will evolve a body of marine rules, constituting a legal system that provides
sufficient legal certainty.
[17] If we take a look on today's practice of international commercial arbitration,
however, we find de-localised and non-public proceedings of ad hoc tribunals
put together by selection of the parties for a single case. No self-reference,
no self-observation, no Autopoiesis in sight? Well, as Niklas Luhmann would
suggest, we ought to search for functional equivalents to continuity and publicity.
[18] Regarding continuity in international commercial arbitration we may find
such functional equivalent in the different arbitration institutions like
the ICC. Strikingly, these institutions sometimes call themselves Court like
the London Court of International Arbitration or the International Court of
Arbitration of the ICC. Although the latter is not a court, since the decision
of a case under the ICC Arbitration Rules remains with the Arbitral Tribunal
which is still put together ad hoc by the parties, it provides an institutional
framework which may be suitable for Autopoiesis. Article 27 of the ICC Rules
provides that each Award before signing shall be submitted in draft to the
Court.(11) The Court exercises a revision with regard to the form of the award,
i.e. binding approval, and a supervision with regard to the substance, i.e.
it may give non-binding advice. The mere fact of a central body auditing every
award, including those applying Lex Mercatoria, may imply the existence of
a institutional memory as described above.
[19] But this memory remains private. Although there is no evidence for a
corresponding practice, under Art. 27 the Court could, for instance, provide
precedent to tribunals dealing with Lex Mercatoria. However, this would not
contribute to legal certainty, as long as the generated rules were not published.
On the other hand, publicity does not necessarily mean public proceedings.
The judgments of the Federal Court of Justice in Germany for instance, are
published generally in an anonymous form regarding the parties and facts of
the case, and often as well in a short form with respect to the legal arguments,
revealing the ratio decidendi rather than any case specific details. There
is something similar as well in international commercial arbitration, e.g.
when some ICC Awards are published in Clunet or involved arbitrators are reporting
on their decisions in law journals.
[20] But the reported materials are still very little and not easy available,
thus preventing the evolution of another feature of Autopoiesis, the self-observation
of a legal system through legal dogmatics in universities, which play an important
role in systematizing the material, offered by adjudication, and in handing
down the knowledge of a legal system to generations of lawyers to come. The
Unidroit- and Lando-Principles do belong into this context. They find their
historical predecessors in the compilations of law, which were published by
private monks in the eleventh century, the time when the western legal tradition
was founded, as Harold Berman in his book on "Law an Revolution"(12)
argued, and when, according to Luhmann, the Autopoiesis of Law emerged for
the first time.
[21] However, these compilations of principles are somehow to abstract, in
that they are not derived from actual adjudication but from the common core
of legal systems as perceived by some famous comparative lawyers. A step further
is the CENTRAL List, which combines the principles with references to arbitral
precedent in Lex Mercatoria.(13) But all these lists become valid law only
by reference of the parties of an international commercial contract. And here
the New Law Merchant is competing with other national private law jurisdictions.
At the end of the day, the international commercial community and, even more
important, its legal advisors have to be convinced, that the New Law Merchant
is a competitive legal system, and that is – as opposed to being merely a
tool of alternative dispute resolution – a normative system reducing transaction
costs in global business by generating legal certainty.
[22] Let me conclude with the following remarks: If asked for advice on the
transformation of the New Law Merchant into an autonomous legal system, Niklas
Luhmann would answer, "the better it works, the better it works."
That is to say: It is all a matter of communication. Or to put it in the words
of a famous German news-speaker: "Do good, and talk about it!" Personally
I have the impression, that in terms of providing free and easy access to
systematic knowledge of Lex Mercatoria and thereby enabling self-reference,
the CENTRAL Transnational Law Database launched today(14) could be a milestone
on the road to the New Law Merchant as an Autopoietic System.
Send this article
Write a comment about this article
? (N) See, e.g. , the contributions to EMERGING LEGAL CERTAINTY: EMPIRICAL
STUDIES ON THE GLOBALIZATION OF LAW (VOLKMAR GESSNER/ALI CEM BUDAK EDS. 1998);
Sally Falk Moore, Law as Process: An Anthropological Approach (1978); idem.,
Law and Social Change: The Semi-Autonomous Legal Field as an Appropriate Field
of Study, in: 7 LAW AND SOCIETY REVIEW 719-746 (1973); Christian Joerges,
Vorüberlegungen zu einer Theorie des internationalen Wirtschaftsrechts, in:
43 RABELSZ 6-79 (1979); Mathias Albert, Introduction: World Society, in: CIVILIZING
WORLD POLITICS. SOCIETY AND COMMUNICATION BYOND THE STATE (M. Albert/L. Brock/Kl.-D.
Wolf Eds. 2000), 1-17; Klaus Günther/Shalini Randeria, RECHT, KULTUR UND GESELLSCHAFT
IM PROZE? DER GLOBALISIERUNG, Werner Reimers Stiftung, Schriftenreihe: Suchprozesse
für innovative Fragestellungen in der Wissenschaft, Heft Nr. 4 (2001); THE
PRACTICE OF TRANSNATIONAL LAW (KLAUS PETER BERGER ED. 2001); Yves Dezalay
& Bryant G. Garth., DEALING IN VIRTUE (1996); Gunther Teubner, GLOBAL
LAW WITHOUT A STATE (1997): idem., Privatregimes: Neo-Spontanes Recht und
duale Sozialverfassungen in der Weltgesellschaft?, in: ZUR AUTONOMIE DES INDIVIDUUMS
– LIBER AMICORUM FüR SPIROS SIMITIS (DIETER SIMON/MANFRED WEISS EDS. 2000),
437-453; Peer Zumbansen, Spiegelungen von ?Staat und Gesellschaft": Governance-Erfahrungen
in der Globalisierungsdebatte, in: STEUERUNGSF?HIGKEIT DES RECHTS UNTER DEN
BEDINGUNGEN DER GLOBALISIERUNG (Anderheiden/Huster/Kirste Eds. 2001), ARSP-Beiheft
79, 13-40.
(1) Presented at the CENTRAL Conference "Transnational Business in the
Age of Globalization" in Muenster, Germany, on October 26, 2001 (www.transnational-law.de).
I want to thank Peer Zumbansen for helpful comments.
(2) G. Teubner, Reflexives Recht, ARCHIV FüR RECHTS- UND SOZIALPHILOSOPHIE, 1982, p. 13et seq.
(3) N. Luhmann, Soziale Systeme, Frankfurt 1984; engl. Social Systems, Stanford UP 1995; N. Luhmann, Das Recht der Gesellschaft, Frankfurt 1993.
(4) J. Habermas, Faktizi?t und Geltung, Frankfurt 1992; engl. Between Facts and Norms, MIT Press 1996.
(5) G. Teubner, Recht als autopoietisches System, Frankfurt 1989; engl. Law as Autopoietic System, London 1993.
(6) See for an extensive discussion of these concepts G. Calliess, Prozedurales Recht 1999.
(7) See the contributions of Berger, Sanders, and Nienaber in: Center for Transnational Law (ed.), Understanding transnational Commercial Arbitration, CENTRAL Practice and Study Guides Vol. 2, Muenster 2000.
(8) K. P. Berger, The New Law Merchant and the Global Market Place, in: Berger (ed.), The Practice of Transnational Law, Kluwer 2001, p.1, 3.
(9) See G. Teubner, "Global Bukowina": Legal Pluralism in the World Society, in: G. Teubner (ed.), Global Law without a State, Dartmouth 1997; G. Teubner, Breaking Frames: The Global Interplay of Legal and Social Systems. THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE LAW 45, 1997, 149; G. Calliess, Globale Kommunikation – staatenloses Recht, Supplement to ARCHIV FüR RECHTS- UND SOZIALPHILOSOPHIE 79 (2001), 61et seq.
(10) Thayer, BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW, 1936, 139, 141; quoted by K. P. Berger, The New Law Merchant and the Global Market Place, op. cit. at 4.
(11) Y. Derains, The ICC Arbitration Rules, in: CENTRAL PRACTICE AND STUDY GUIDES Vol. 2, 58
(12) Harold J. Berman, Law and Revolution. The Formation of the Western Legal Tradition, p.85, 87 (1983); in German: Recht und Revolution, Frankfurt 1991.
(13) K. P. Berger, Formalisierte oder schleichende Kodifizierung des transnationalen
Wirtschaftsrechts, Berlin 1996; Engl. The Creeping Codification of the Lex
Mercatoria, Kluwer 1999.
See www.tldb.de and www.transnational-law.de