公 法 评 论 |
惟愿公平如大水滚滚,使公义如江河滔滔! |
Inaugural Lecture at Freiburg im Breisgau
1917
Pure Phenomenology, Its Method and Its Field of Investigation
Edmund Husserl
Ladies and gentlemen, honored colleagues, dear comrades!
[1] In all the areas within which the spiritual life of humanity is at work, the historical epoch wherein fate has placed us is an epoch of stupendous happenings. Whatever previous generations cultivated by their toil and struggle into a harmonious whole, in every sphere of culture, whatever enduring style was deemed established as method and norm, is once more in flux and now seeks new forms whereby reason, as yet unsatisfied, may develop more freely: in politics, in economic life, in technics, in the fine arts, and--by no means least of all--in the sciences. In a few decades of reconstruction, even the mathematical natural sciences, the ancient archetypes of theoretical perfection, have changed habit completely!
[2] Philosophy, too, fits into this picture. In philosophy, the forms whose
energies were dissipated in the period following the overthrow of Hegelian
philosophy were essentially those of a renaissance. They were forms that reclaimed
past philosophies, and their methods as well as some of their essential content
originated with great thinkers of the past.
[3] Most recently, the need for an utterly original philosophy has re-emerged,
the need of a philosophy that--in contrast to the secondary productivity of
renaissance philosophies--seeks by radically clarifying the sense and the
motifs of philosophical problems to penetrate to that primal ground on whose
basis those problems must find whatever solution is genuinely scientific.
[4] A new fundamental science, pure phenomenology, has developed within philosophy:
This is a science of a thoroughly new type and endless scope. It is inferior
in methodological rigor to none of the modern sciences. All philosophical
disciplines are rooted in pure phenomenology, through whose development, and
through it alone, they obtain their proper force. Philosophy is possible as
a rigorous science at all only through pure phenomenology. It is of pure phenomenology
I wish to speak: the intrinsic nature of its method and its subject matter
that is invisible to naturally oriented points of view.
[5] Pure phenomenology claims to be the science of pure phenomena. This concept
of the phenomenon, which was developed under various names as early as the
eighteenth century without being clarified, is what we shall have to deal
with first of all.
[6] We shall begin with the necessary correlation between object, truth, and
cognition--using these words in their very broadest senses. To every object
there correspond an ideally closed system of truths that are true of it and,
on the other hand, an ideal system of possible cognitive processes by virtue
of which the object and the truths about it would be given to any cognitive
subject. Let us consider these processes. At the lowest cognitive level, they
are processes of experiencing, or, to speak more generally, processes of intuiting
that grasp the object in the original.
[7] Something similar is obviously true of all types of intuitions and of
all other processes of meaning an object even when they have the character
of mere re-presentations that (like rememberings or pictorial intuitions or
processes of meaning something symbolic) do not have the intrinsic character
of being conscious of the intuited's being there "in person" but
are conscious of it instead as recalled, as re-presented in the picture or
by means of symbolic indications and the like, and even when the actuality
valuation of the intuited varies in some, no matter what, manner. Even intuitions
in phantasy, therefore, are intrinsically intuitions of objects and carry
"object phenomena" with them intrinsically, phenomena that are obviously
not characterized as actualities. If higher, theoretical cognition is to begin
at al, objects belonging to the sphere in question must be intuited. Natural
objects, for example, must be experienced before any theorizing about them
can occur. Experiencing is consciousness that intuits something and values
it to be actual; experiencing is intrinsically characterized as consciousness
of the natural object in question and of it as the original: there is consciousness
of the original as being there "in person." The same thing can be
expressed by saying that objects would be nothing at all for the cognizing
subject if they did not "appear" to him, if he had of them no "phenomenon."
Here, therefore, "phenomenon" signifies a certain content that intrinsically
inhabits the intuitive consciousness in question and is the substrate for
its actuality valuation.
[8] Something similar is still true of the courses followed by manifold intuitions
which together make up the unity of one continuous consciousness of one and
the same object. The manner in which the object is given within each of the
single intuitions belonging to this continuous consciousness may vary constantly;
for example, the object's sensuous "looks"--the way in which the
object always "looks" different at each approach or remove and at
every turning, from above or below, from left or right--may be forever new
in the transition from one perception to continuously new perceptions. In
spite of that, we have, in the way in which such series of perceptions with
their changing sensuous images take their courses, intuitive consciousness
not of a changing multiplicity but rather of one and the same object that
is variously presented. To put it differently, within the pure immanence of
such consciousness one unitary "phenomenon" permeates all the manifolds
of phenomenal presentation. It is the peculiar characteristic of such states
of affairs which makes for the shift in the concept "phenomenon."
Rather than just the thoroughgoing unity of intuition, the variously, changing
modes in which the unity is present, e.g. , the continuously changing perspectival
looks of a real object, are also called "phenomena."
[9] The extent of this concept is further broadened when we consider the higher
cognitive functions: the multiform acts and coherency of referential, combinative,
conceiving, theorizing cognition. Every single process of any of these sorts
is, again, intrinsically consciousness of the object that is peculiar to it
as a thought process of some particular sort of sorts; hence, the object is
characterized as member of a combination, as either subject or relatum of
a relation, etc. The single cognitive processes, on the other hand combine
in the unity of one consciousness that constitutes intrinsically a single
synthetic objectivity, a single predicative state-of-affairs, for example,
or a single theoretical context, an object such as is expressed in sentences
like: "The object is related in this or that way," "It is a
whole composed of these and those parts," "The relationship B derives
from the relationship A," etc.
[10] Consciousness of all synthetically objective formations of these kinds
occurs through such multimembered acts that unite to form higher unities of
consciousness, and it occurs by means of immanently constituted phenomena
that function at the same time as substrates for differing valuations, such
as certain truth, probability, possibility, etc.
[11] The concept "phenomenon" carries over, furthermore, to the
changing modes of being conscious of something--for example, the clear and
the obscure, evident and blind modes--in which one and the same relation or
connection, one and the same state-of-affairs, one and the same logical coherency,
etc., can be given to consciousness.
[12] In summary, the first and most primitive concept of the phenomenon referred
to the limited sphere of those sensuously given realities [der sinnendinglichen
Gegebenheiten] through which Nature is evinced in perceiving.
[13] The concept was extended, without comment, to include every kind of sensuously
meant or objectivated thing. It was then extended to include also the sphere
of those synthetic objectivities that are given to consciousness through referential
and connective conscious syntheses. It thus includes all modes in which things
are give to consciousness And it was seen finally to include the whole realm
of consciousness with all of the ways of being conscious of something and
all the constituents that can be shown immanently to belong to them. That
the concept includes all ways of conscious of something means that it includes,
as well, every sort of feeling, desiring, and willing with its immanent "comportment"
[Verhalten].
[14] To understand this broadening of the concept is very easy if one considers
that emotional and volitional processes also have intrinsically the character
of being conscious of something and that enormous categories of objects, including
all cultural objects, all values, all goods, all works, can be experienced,
understood, and made objective as such only through the participation of emotional
and volitional consciousness. No object of the category "work of art"
could occur in the objectivational world of any being who was devoid of all
aesthetic sensibility, who was, so to speak, aesthetically blind.
[15] Through this exposition of the concept of "phenomenon" we obtain
a preliminary conception of a general phenomenology, viz., a science of objective
phenomena of every kind, the science of every kind of object, an "object"
being taken purely as something having just those determinations with which
it presents itself in consciousness and in just those changing modes through
which it so presents itself. It would be the task of phenomenology, therefore,
to investigate how something perceived, something remembered, something phantasied,
something pictorially represented, something symbolized looks as such, i.e.,
to investigate how it looks by virtue of that bestowal of sense and of characteristics
which is carried out intrinsically by the perceiving, the remembering, the
phantasying, the pictorial representing, etc., itself. Obviously, phenomenology
would investigate in the same way how what is collected looks in the collecting
of it; what is disjoined, in the disjoining, what is produced, in the producing;
and, similarly, for every act of thinking, how it intrinsically "has"
phenomenally in it what it thinks; how, in aesthetic valuing, the valued looks
as such; in actively shaping something, the shaped as such; etc. What phenomenology
wants, in all these investigations, is to establish what admits of being stated
with the universal validity of theory. In doing so, however, its investigations
will, understandably, have to refer to the intrinsic nature [das eigene Wesen]
of the perceiving itself, of remembering (or any other way of representing)
itself, and of thinking, valuing, willing, and doing themselves--these acts
being taken just as they present themselves to immanently intuitive reflection.
In Cartesian terms, the investigation will be concerned with the cogito in
its own right as well as with the cogitatum qua cogitatum. As the two are
inseparable involved with each other in being, so, understandably, are they
in the investigation as well.
[16] If these are the themes of phenomenology, then it can also be called
"science of consciousness," if consciousness be taken purely as
such.
[17] To characterize this science more exactly, we shall introduce a simple
distinction between phenomena and Objects [Objekten]* in the pregnant sense
of the word. In general logical parlance, any subject whatever of true predications
is an object. In this sense, therefore, every phenomenon is also an object.
Within this widest concept of object, and specifically within the concept
of individual object, Objects and phenomena stand in contrast with each other.
Objects [Objekte], all natural Objects, for example, are objects foreign to
consciousness. Consciousness does, indeed, objectivate them and posit them
as actual, yet the consciousness that experiences them and takes cognizance
of them is so singularly astonishing that it bestows upon its own phenomena
the sense of being appearances of Objects foreign to consciousness and knows
these "extrinsic" Objects through processes that take cognizance
of their sense. Those objects that are neither conscious processor nor immanent
constituents of conscious processes we therefore call Objects in the pregnant
sense of the word.
[18] This places two separate sciences in the sharpest of contrasts: on the
one hand, phenomenology, the science of consciousness as it is in itself;
on the other, the "Objective" sciences as a totality.
[19] To the objects which are obviously correlated to each other, of these
contrasted sciences there correspond two fundamentally different types of
experience and of intuition generally: immanent experience and Objective experience,
also called "external" or transcendent experience. Immanent experience
consists in the mere viewing that takes place in reflection by which consciousness
and that of which there is consciousness are grasped. For example, a liking
or a desiring that I am just now executing enters into my experience by way
of a merely retrospective look and, by means of this look, is given absolutely.
What "absolutely" means here we can learn by contrast: we can experience
any external thing only insofar as it presents itself to us sensuously through
this or that adumbration [Abschattung]. A liking has no changing presentations;
there are no changing perspectives on or views of it as if it might be seen
from above or below, from near or far. It just is nothing foreign to consciousness
at all that could present itself to consciousness through the mediation of
phenomena different from the liking itself; to like is intrinsically to be
conscious.
[20] This is involved with the fact that the existence of what is given to
immanent reflection is indubitable while what is experienced through external
experience always allows the possibility that it may prove to be an illusory
Object in the course of further experiences.
[21] Immanent and transcendent experience are nevertheless connected in a
remarkable way: by a change in attitude, we can pass from the one to the other.
[22] In the natural attitude, we experience, among other things, processes
in Nature [Natur]; we are adverted to them, observe them, describe them, subsume
them under concepts [bestimmen sie]. While we do so, there occur in our experiencing
and theorizing consciousness multiform conscious processes which have constantly
changing immanent constituents. The things involved present themselves through
continuously flowing aspects; their shapes are perspectivally silhouetted
[schatten sich ab] in definite ways; the data of the different senses are
construed in definite ways, e.g., as unitary colorings of the experiences
shapes or as warmth radiating from them; the sensuous qualities construed
are referred, by being construed referentially and causally, to real circumstances;
etc. The bestowing of each of these senses is carried out in consciousness
and by virtue of definite series of flowing conscious processes. A person
in the natural attitude, whoever, knows nothing of this. He executes the acts
of experiencing, referring, combining; but, while he is executing them, he
is looking not toward them but rather in the direction of the objects he is
conscious of.
[23] On the other hand, he can convert his natural attentional focus into
the phenomenologically reflective one; he can make the currently flowing consciousness
and, thus, the infinitely multiform world of phenomena at large the theme
of his fixating observations, descriptions, theoretical investigations--the
investigations which, for short, we call "phenomenological."
[24] At this point, however, there arises what, in the present situation of
philosophy, can be called the most decisive of questions. Is not what was
just described as immanent reflection simply identical with internal, psychological
experience? Is not psychology the proper place for the investigation of consciousness
and all its phenomena? However much psychology may previously have omitted
any systematic investigation of consciousness, however blindly it may have
passed over all radical problems concerning the bestowal, carried out in the
immanence of consciousness, objective sense, it still seems clear that such
investigations should belong to psychology and should even be fundamental
to it.
[25] The ideal of a pure phenomenology will be perfected only by answering
this question; pure phenomenology is to be separated sharply from psychology
at large and, specifically, from the descriptive psychology of the phenomena
of consciousness. Only with this separation does the centuries-old conflict
over "psychologism" reach its final conclusion. The conflict is
over nothing less than the true philosophical method and the foundation of
any philosophy as pure and strict science.
[26] To begin with, we put the proposition: pure phenomenology is the science
of pure consciousness. This means that pure phenomenology draws upon pure
reflection exclusively, and pure reflection excludes, as such, every type
of external experience and therefore precludes any copositing of objects alien
to consciousness. Psychology, on the other hand, is science of psychic Nature
and, therefore, of consciousness as Nature or as real event in the spatiotemporal
world. Psychology draws upon psychological experiencing, which is an apperceiving
that links immanent reflection to experience of the external, the extrinsic
[?usserer Erfahrung]. In psychological experience, moreover, the psychic is
given as event within the cohesion of Nature. Specifically, psychology, as
the natural science of psychic life, regards conscious processes as the conscious
processes of animate being, i.e., as real causal adjuncts to animate bodies.
The psychologist must resort to reflection in order to have conscious processes
experientially given. Nevertheless, this reflection does not keep to pure
reflection; for, in being taken as belonging really to the animate body in
question, reflection is linked to experience of the extrinsic. Psychologically
experienced consciousness is therefore no longer pure consciousness; construed
Objectively in this way, consciousness itself becomes something transcendent,
becomes an event in that spatial world which appears, by virtue of consciousness,
to be transcendent.
[27] The fundamental fact is that there is a kind of intuiting which--in contrast
to psychological experiencing--remains within pure reflection: pure reflection
excludes everything that is given in the natural attitude and excludes therefore
all of Nature.
[28] Consciousness is taken purely as it intrinsically is with its own intrinsic
constituents, and no being that transcends consciousness is coposited.
[29] What is thematically posited is only what is given, by pure reflection,
with all its immanent essential moments absolutely as it is given to pure
reflection.
[30] Descartes long ago came close to discovering the purely phenomenological
sphere. He did so in his famous and fundamental meditation--that has nevertheless
been basically fruitless--which culminates in the much quoted "ego cogito,
ego sum." The so-called phenomenological reduction can be effected by
modifying Descartes's method, by carrying it through purely and consequentially
while disregarding all Cartesian aims; phenomenological reduction is the method
for effecting radical purification of the phenomenological field of consciousness
from all obtrusions from Objective actualities and for keeping it pure of
them. Consider the following: Nature, the universe of spatiotemporal Objectivity,
is given to us constantly; in the natural attitude, it already is the field
for our investigations in the natural sciences and for our practical purposes.
Yet, nothing prevents us from putting out of action, so to speak, any believing
in the actuality of it, even though that believing continues to occur all
the while in our mental processes. After all, speaking quite universally,
no believing, no conviction, however evident, excludes by its essence the
possibility of its being put in a certain way out of action or deprived of
its force. What this means we can learn from any case in which we examine
one of our convictions, perhaps to defend it against objections or to re-establish
it on a new basis. It may be that we have no doubts at all about it. Yet,
we obviously alter during the whole course of the examination the way we act
in relation to this conviction. Without surrendering our conviction in the
least, we still do not take part in it; we deny to ourselves acceptance, as
truth, of what the conviction posits simply to be true. While the examination
is being carried out, this truth is in question; it remains to be seen; it
is to remain undecided.
[31] In our instance, in the case of phenomenologically pure reflection, the
aim is not to place in question and to test our believing in actualities foreign
to consciousness. Nevertheless, we can carry out a similar putting-out-of-action
for that consciousness of actuality by virtue of which the whole of Nature
is existence which, for us, is given [für uns gegebenes Dasein ist]; and we
can do so utterly ad libitum. For the sole purposes of attaining to the domain
of pure consciousness and keeping it pure, we therefore undertake to accept
no beliefs involving Objective experience and, therefore, also undertake to
make not the slightest use of any conclusion derived from Objective experience.
[32] The actuality of all of material Nature is therefore kept out of action
and that of all corporeality along with it, including the actuality of my
body, the body of the cognizing subject.
[33] This makes it clear that, as a consequence, all psychological experience
is also put out of action. If we have absolutely forbidden ourselves to treat
Nature and the corporeal at all as given actualities, then the possibility
of positing any conscious process whatsoever as having a corporeal link or
as being an event occurring in Nature lapses of itself.
[34] What is left over, once this radical methodological exclusion of all
Objective actualities has been effected? The answer is clear. If we put every
experienced actuality out of action, we still have indubitably given every
phenomenon of experience. This is true for the whole Objective world as well.
We are forbidden to make use of the actuality of the Objective world; for,
the Objective world is as if it were placed in brackets. What remains to us
is the totality of the phenomena of the world, phenomena which are grasped
by reflection as they are absolutely in themselves [in ihrer absoluten Selbstheit].
For, all of these constituents of conscious life remain intrinsically what
they were; it is through them that the world is constituted.
[35] So far as their own phenomenal content is concerned, they do not suffer
in any way when believing in Objective actuality is put out of play. Nor does
reflection, insofar as it grasps and views the phenomena in their own being,
suffer in any way. Only now, in fact, does reflection become pure and exclusive.
Moreover, even the belief in the Objective, the belief characteristic of simple
experience and of empirical theory, is not lost to us. Instead, it becomes
our theme just as it intrinsically is and in accord with what is implicit
in it as its sense and as the substrate for what it posits; we view the belief;
we analyze its immanent character; we follow its possible coherences, especially
those of grounding; we study in pure reflection what takes place in transitions
to fulfilling insight, what is preserved of the meant sense in such transitions,
what the fullness of intuition brings to this sense, what alteration and enrichment
so-called evidence contributes, and whatever advances are made by what, in
this connection, is called "attaining Objective truth through insight."
Following this method of phenomenological reduction (i.e., keeping out of
action all believing in the transcendent), every kind of theoretical, valuational,
practical consciousness can be made in the same manner a theme of inquiry;
and all the Objectivities constituted in it can be investigated. The investigation
will take these Objectivities simply as correlates of consciousness and will
inquire solely into the What and the How of the phenomena that can be drawn
from the conscious processes and coherencies in question. Things in Nature,
persons and personal communities, social forms and formations, poetic and
plastic formations, every kind of cultural work--all become in this way headings
for phenomenological investigations, not as actualities, the way they are
treated in the corresponding Objective sciences, but rather with regard to
the consciousness that constitutes--through the intermediary of an initially
bewildering wealth of structures of consciousness--these objectivities for
the conscious subject in question. Consciousness and what it is conscious
of is therefore what is left over as field for pure reflection once phenomenological
reduction has been effected: the endless multiplicity of manners of being
conscious, on the one hand, and, on the other, the infinity of intentional
correlates. What keeps us from transgressing this field is the index that,
thanks to the method of phenomenological reduction every Objective belief
obtains as soon as it arises for consciousness. The index demands of us: Take
no part in this belief; do not fall into the attitude of Objective science;
keep to the pure phenomenon! Obviously, the index is universal in the scope
in which it suspends acceptance of the Objective sciences themselves, of which
psychology is one. The index changes all sciences to science phenomena; and,
in this status, they are among its larger themes.
[36] However, as soon as any proposition about things Objective, any one at
all, including even the most indubitable truth, is claimed to be a valid truth,
the soil of pure phenomenology is abandoned. For then we take our stance upon
some Objective soil and carry on psychology or some other Objective science
instead of phenomenology.
[37] This radical suspension of Nature stands in conflict, to be sure, with
our most deeply rooted habits of experience and thinking. Yet it is precisely
for this reason that fully self-conscious phenomenological reduction is needed
if consciousness is to be systematically investigated in its pure immanence
at all.
[38] But still other reservations come to mind. Is pure phenomenology genuinely
possible as a science, and, if so, then how? Once the suspension is in effect,
we are left with pure consciousness. In pure consciousness, however, what
we find is an unresting flow of never recurring phenomena, even though they
may be indubitably given in reflective experience. Experience by itself is
not science. Since the reflecting and cognizing subject has only his flowing
phenomena genuinely and since every other cognizing subject--his corporeality
and consequently his consciousness [seinem Erleben] as well--falls within
the scope of the exclusion, how can an empirical science still be possible?
Science cannot be solipsistic. It must be valid for every experience subject.
[39] We would be in a nasty position indeed if empirical science were the
only kind of science possible. Answering the question we have posed thus leads
to most profound and as yet unsolved philosophical problems. Be that as it
may, pure phenomenology was not established to be an empirical science, and
what it calls its 'purity' is not just that of pure reflection but is at the
same time the entirely different sort of purity we meet in the names of other
sciences.
[40] We often speak in a general, and intelligible, way of pure mathematics,
pure arithmetic, pure geometry, pure kinematics, etc. These we contrast, as
a priori sciences, to sciences, such as the natural sciences, based on experience
and induction. Sciences that are pure in this sense, a priori sciences, are
pure of any assertion about empirical actuality. Intrinsically, they purport
to be concerned with the ideally possible and the pure laws thereof rather
than with actualities. In contrast to them, empirical sciences are sciences
of the de facto actual, which is given as such through experience.
[41] Now, just as pure analysis does not treat of actual things and their
de facto magnitudes but investigates instead the essential laws pertaining
to the essence of any possible quantity, or just as pure geometry is bound
to shapes observed in actual experience but instead inquires into possible
shapes and their possible transformations, constructing ad libitum in pure
geometric phantasy, and establishes their essential laws, in precisely the
same way pure phenomenology proposes to investigate the realm of pure consciousness
and its phenomena not as de facto exists but as pure possibilities with their
pure laws. And, indeed, when one becomes familiar with the soil of pure reflection,
one is compelled to the view that possibilities are subject to ideal laws
in the realm of pure consciousness as well. For example, the pure phenomena
through which a possible spatial Object presents itself to consciousness have
their a priori definite system of necessary formations which is unconditionally
binding upon every cognizing consciousness if that consciousness is to be
able to intuit spatial reality. [Raumdinglichket]. Thus, the ideal of a spatial
thing prescribes a priori to possible consciousness of such a thing a set
rule, a rule that can be followed intuitively and that admits of being conceived,
in accord with the typicality of phenomenal forms, in pure concepts. And the
same is true of every principal category of objectivities. The expression
'a priori' is therefore not a cloak to cover some ideological extravagance
but is just as significant as is the 'purity' of mathematical analysis or
geometry.
[42] Obviously, I can here offer no more than this helpful analogy. Without
troublesome work, no one can have any concrete, full idea of what pure mathematical
research is like or of the profusion of insights that can be obtained from
it. The same sort of penetrating work, for which no general characterization
can adequately substitute, is required if one is to understand phenomenological
science concretely. That the work is worthwhile can readily be seen from the
unique position of phenomenology with regard to philosophy on the one hand
and psychology on the other. Pure phenomenology's tremendous significance
for any concrete grounding of psychology is clear from the very beginning.
If all consciousness is subject to essential laws in a manner similar to that
in which spatial reality is subject to mathematical laws, then these essential
laws will be of most fertile significance in investigating facts of the conscious
life of human and brute animals.
[43] So far as philosophy is concerned, it is enough to point out that all
ratio-theoretical [vernunft-theoretischen] problems, the problems involved
in the so-called critique of theoretical, valuational, and practical reason,
are concerned entirely with essential coherences prevailing between theoretical,
axiological, or practical Objectivity and the consciousness in which it is
immanently constituted. It is easy to demonstrate that ratio-theoretical problems
can be formulated with scientific rigor and can then be solved in their systematic
coherence only on the soil of phenomenologically pure consciousness and within
the framework of a pure phenomenology. The critique of reason and all philosophical
problems along with it can be put on the course of strict science by a kind
of research that draws intuitively upon what is given phenomenologically but
not by thinking of the kind that plays out value concepts, a game played with
constructions far removed from intuition.
[44] Philosophers, as things now stand, are all too fond of offering criticism
from on high instead of studying and understanding things from within. They
often behave toward phenomenology as Berkeley--otherwise a brilliant philosopher
and psychologist--behaved two centuries ago toward the then newly established
infinitesimal calculus. He thought that he could prove, by his logically sharp
but superficial criticism, this sort of mathematical analysis to be a completely
groundless extravagance, a vacuous game played with empty abstractions. It
is utterly beyond doubt that phenomenology, new and most fertile, will overcome
all resistance and stupidity and will enjoy enormous development, just as
the infinitesimal mathematics that was so alien to its contemporaries did,
and just as exact physics, in opposition to the brilliantly obscure natural
philosophy of the Renaissance, has done since the time of Galileo.
*Following the practice of Dorion Cairns in his translation of Husserl's Cartesian Meditations, the word 'object', spelled with a small letter, has been and will be used throughout to translate Gegenstand, spelled with a capital letter, it translates Objekt. In the same way, words derived from Gegenstand or from Objekt will be translated with words derived from 'object', spelled with a small or with a capital letter, repectively. Where 'object' or one of its derivativeds is the initial word in a sentence, the German word will be given in brackets. The practice appears to be justified perfectly by the manner in which the text proceeds to differentiate between the senses of Gegenstand and Objekt.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
Translated by Robert Welsh Jordan. Husserl: Shorter Works. Edited by Peter McCormick and Frederick A. Elliston. Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981.